"Mighty is geometry; joined with art, irresistible." (Euripides,. 5th century BC)
"The knowledge of which geometry aims is the knowledge of the eternal." (Plato, "Republic", 4th century BC)
"And so they have handed down to us clear knowledge of the speed of the heavenly bodies and their risings and settings, of geometry, numbers and, not least, of the science of music. For these sciences seem to be related." (Archytas of Tarentym, 4th century BC)
"Thus, of all the honorable arts, which are carried out either naturally or proceed in imitation of nature, geometry takes the skill of reasoning as its field. It is hard at the beginning and difficult of access, delightful in its order, full of beauty, unsurpassable in its effect. For with its clear processes of reasoning it illuminates the field of rational thinking, so that it may be understood that geometry belongs to the arts or that the arts are from geometry." (Agennius Urbicus, "Controversies about Fields", cca. 4 century BC)
"It is not possible to find in all geometry more difficult and more intricate questions or more simple and lucid explanations [than those given by Archimedes]. Some ascribe this to his natural genius; while others think that incredible effort and toil produced these, to all appearance, easy and unlaboured results. No amount of investigation of yours would succeed in attaining the proof, and yet, once seen, you immediately believe you would have discovered it; by so smooth and so rapid a path he leads you to the conclusion required." (Plutarch, cca. 1st century)
"The Pythagoreans considered all mathematical science to be divided into four parts: one half they marked off as concerned with quantity, the other half with magnitude; and each of these they posited as twofold. A quantity can be considered in regard to its character by itself or in relation to another quantity, magnitudes as either stationary or in motion. Arithmetic, then, studies quantity as such, music the relations between quantities, geometry magnitude at rest, spherics magnitude inherently moving." (Proclus Lycaeus, cca. 5th century)
"It is essential that the treatment [of geometry] should be rid of everything superfluous, for the superfluous is an obstacle to the acquisition of knowledge; it should select everything that embraces the subject and brings it to a focus, for this is of the highest service to science; it must have great regard both to clearness and to conciseness, for their opposites trouble our understanding; it must aim to generalize its theorems, for the division of knowledge into small elements renders it difficult of comprehension." (Proclus Lycaeus, cca. 5th century)
"Mathematical science […] has these divisions: arithmetic, music, geometry, astronomy. Arithmetic is the discipline of absolute numerable quantity. Music is the discipline which treats of numbers in their relation to those things which are found in sound." (Cassiodorus, cca. 6th century)
"Geometry enlightens the intellect and sets one’s mind right. All of its proofs are very clear and orderly. It is hardly possible for errors to enter into geometrical reasoning, because it is well arranged and orderly. Thus, the mind that constantly applies itself to geometry is not likely to fall into error. In this convenient way, the person who knows geometry acquires intelligence." (Ibn Khaldun, "The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History", 1377)
"Geometry enlightens the intellect and sets one's mind right. All of its proofs are very clear and orderly. It is hardly possible for errors to enter into geometrical reasoning, because it is well arranged and orderly. Thus, the mind that constantly applies itself to geometry is not likely to fall into error. In this convenient way, the person who knows geometry acquires intelligence." (Ibn Khaldun, cca. 14th century)
"[…] geometry is the right foundation of all painting […]" (Albrecht Dürer, "Course in the Art of Measurement", 1525)
“Where there is matter, there is geometry.” (Johannes Kepler, “Concerning the More Certain Fundamentals of Astrology”, 1601)
“Geometry is one and eternal shining in the mind of God.” (Johannes Kepler, “Conversation with the Sidereal Messenger” [an open letter to Galileo Galilei] 1610)
"Indeed, many geometric things can be discovered or elucidated by algebraic principles, and yet it does not follow that algebra is geometrical, or even that it is based on geometric principles (as some would seem to think). This close affinity of arithmetic and geometry comes about, rather, because geometry is, as it were, subordinate to arithmetic, and applies universal principles of arithmetic to its special objects." (John Wallis, "Mathesis Universalis", 1657)
"Only geometry can hand us the thread [which will lead us through] the labyrinth of the continuum's composition, the maximum and the minimum, the infinitesimal and the infinite; and no one will arrive at a truly solid metaphysics except he who has passed through this [labyrinth]." (Gottfried W Leibniz, "Dissertatio Exoterica De Statu Praesenti et Incrementis Novissimis Deque Usu Geometriae", 1676)
"The Excellence of Modern Geometry is in nothing more evident, than in those full and adequate Solutions it gives to Problems; representing all possible Cases in one view, and in one general Theorem many times comprehending whole Sciences; which deduced at length into Propositions, and demonstrated after the manner of the Ancients, might well become the subjects of large Treatises: For whatsoever Theorem solves the most complicated Problem of the kind, does with a due Reduction reach all the subordinate Cases." (Edmund Halley, "An Instance of the Excellence of Modern Algebra in the resolution of the problem of finding the foci of optic glasses universally", Philosophical Transactions, 1694)
"The branch of geometry that deals with magnitudes has been zealously studied throughout the past, but there is another branch that has been almost unknown up to now; Leibniz spoke of it first, calling it the ‘geometry of position’ (geometria situs). This branch of geometry deals with relations dependent on position; it does not take magnitudes into considerations, nor does it involve calculation with quantities. But as yet no satisfactory definition has been given of the problems that belong to this geometry of position or of the method to be used in solving them." (Leonhard Euler, 1735)
"Show all these fanatics a little geometry, and they learn it quite easily. But, strangely enough, their minds are not thereby rectified. They perceive the truths of geometry, but it does not teach them to weighp robabilities. Their minds have set hard. They will reason in a topsy-turvy wall all their lives, and I am sorry for it." (Voltaire, "Philosophical Dictionary", 1764)
"We admit, in geometry, not only infinite magnitudes, that is to say, magnitudes greater than any assignable magnitude, but infinite magnitudes infinitely greater, the one than the other. This astonishes our dimension of brains, which is only about six inches long, five broad, and six in depth, in the largest heads." (Voltaire, "Philosophical Dictionary", 1764)
“I am ever more convinced that the necessity of our geometry cannot be proved - at least not by human reason for human reason. It is possible that in another lifetime we will arrive at other conclusions on the nature of space that we now have no access to. In the meantime we must not put geometry on a par with arithmetic that exists purely a priori but rather with mechanics.” (Carl F Gauss, [letter to Heinrich W Olbers] 1817)
"The doctrines of pure geometry often, and in many questions, give a simple and natural way to penetrate to the origin of truths, to lay bare the mysterious chain which unites them, and to make them known individually, luminously and completely.” (Michek Chasles, “Aperçu historique sur l'origine et le développement des méthodes en géométrie", 1837)
"Every theorem in geometry is a law of external nature, and might have been ascertained by generalizing from observation and experiment, which in this case resolve themselves into comparisons and measurements. But it was found practicable, and being practicable was desirable, to deduce these truths by ratiocination from a small number of general laws of nature, the certainty and universality of which was obvious to the most careless observer, and which compose the first principles and ultimate premises of the science." (John S Mill, "System of Logic", 1843)
"Arithmetic has for its object the properties of number in the abstract. In algebra, viewed as a science of operations, order is the predominating idea. The business of geometry is with the evolution of the properties of space, or of bodies viewed as existing in space." (James J Sylvester, "A Probationary Lecture on Geometry", 1844)
"The connected course of reasoning by which any Geometrical truth is established is called a demonstration." (Robert Potts, "Euclid's Elements of Geometry", 1845)
"In all cases, however, it must be kept in view that every geometrical truth is deduced by a comparison between two others, which agree, one in one particular part, and the other in another, with the conclusion so deduced." (?,"Miscallanea Mathematica", American Railroad Journal, No. X, 1846)
"It is well known that geometry presupposes not only the concept of space but also the first fundamental notions for constructions in space as given in advance. It only gives nominal definitions for them, while the essential means of determining them appear in the form of axioms. The relationship of these presumptions is left in the dark; one sees neither whether and in how far their connection is necessary, nor a priori whether it is possible." (Bernhard Riemann, "On the hypotheses which lie at the foundation of geometry", 1854)
"Mathematics is peculiarly and preeminently the science of relations, and whether quantity or direction may severally form its object, these are never contemplated in characters purely absolute, but invariably in comparison with other objects like themselves; and it is hence that relations once established by the unerring theorems of the science, we are enabled, disregarding magnitude in itself, to pass indifferently from the finite to the infinite, from the limited regions of sense to those of conception, and with all the assurance and all the certainty that even the geometry of the ancients could confer." (John H W Waugh, Mathematical Essays", 1854)
“Geometry in every proposition speaks a language which experience never dares to utter; and indeed of which she but half comprehends the meaning. Experience sees that the assertions are true, but she sees not how profound and absolute is their truth. She unhesitatingly assents to the laws which geometry delivers, but she does not pretend to see the origin of their obligation. She is always ready to acknowledge the sway of pure scientific principles as a matter of fact, but she does not dream of offering her opinion on their authority as a matter of right; still less can she justly claim to herself the source of that authority.” (William Whewell, “The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences”, 1858)
"This science, Geometry, is one of indispensable use and constant reference, for every student of the laws of nature; for the relations of space and number are the alphabet in which those laws are written. But besides the interest and importance of this kind which geometry possesses, it has a great and peculiar value for all who wish to understand the foundations of human knowledge, and the methods by which it is acquired. For the student of geometry acquires, with a degree of insight and clearness which the unmathematical reader can but feebly imagine, a conviction that there are necessary truths, many of them of a very complex and striking character; and that a few of the most simple and self-evident truths which it is possible for the mind of man to apprehend, may, by systematic deduction, lead to the most remote and unexpected results." (William Whewell, "The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences", 1858)
“When we consider that the whole of geometry rests ultimately on axioms which derive their validity from the nature of our intuitive faculty, we seem well justified in questioning the sense of imaginary forms, since we attribute to them properties which not infrequently contradict all our intuitions.” (Gottlob Frege, “On a Geometrical Representation of Imaginary forms in the Plane”, 1873)
“[…] with few exceptions all the operations and concepts that occur in the case of real numbers can indeed be carried over unchanged to complex ones. However, the concept of being greater cannot very well be applied to complex numbers. In the case of integration, too, there appear differences which rest on the multplicity of possible paths of integration when we are dealing with complex variables. Nevertheless, the large extent to which imaginary forms conform to the same laws as real ones justifies the introduction of imaginary forms into geometry.” (Gottlob Frege, “On a Geometrical Representation of Imaginary forms in the Plane”, 1873)
“When we consider complex numbers and their geometrical representation, we leave the field of the original concept of quantity, as contained especially in the quantities of Euclidean geometry: its lines, surfaces and volumes. According to the old conception, length appears as something material which fills the straight line between its end points and at the same time prevents another thing from penetrating into its space by its rigidity. In adding quantities, we are therefore forced to place one quantity against another. Something similar holds for surfaces and solid contents. The introduction of negative quantities made a dent in this conception, and imaginary quantities made it completely impossible. Now all that matters is the point of origin and the end point; whether there is a continuous line between them, and if so which, appears to make no difference whatsoever; the idea of filling space has been completely lost. All that has remained is certain general properties of addition, which now emerge as the essential characteristic marks of quantity. The concept has thus gradually freed itself from intuition and made itself independent. This is quite unobjectionable, especially since its earlier intuitive character was at bottom mere appearance. Bounded straight lines and planes enclosed by curves can certainly be intuited, but what is quantitative about them, what is common to lengths and surfaces, escapes our intuition.” (Gottlob Frege, “Methods of Calculation based on an Extension of the Concept of Quantity”, 1874)
“Algebra is but written geometry and geometry is but figured algebra.” (Sophie Germain, Mémoire sur les Surfaces Élastiques”, 1880)
“In geometry, as in most sciences, it is very rare that an isolated proposition is of immediate utility. But the theories most powerful in practice are formed of propositions which curiosity alone brought to light, and which long remained useless without its being able to divine in what way they should one day cease to be so. In this sense it may be said, that in real science, no theory, no research, is in effect useless.” (Voltaire, “A Philosophical Dictionary”, 1881)
“We admit, in geometry, not only infinite magnitudes, that is to say, magnitudes greater than any assignable magnitude, but infinite magnitudes infinitely greater, the one than the other. This astonishes our dimension of brains, which is only about six inches long, five broad, and six in depth, in the largest heads.” (Voltaire, “A Philosophical Dictionary”, 1881)
“Geometry exhibits the most perfect example of logical stratagem.” (Henry T Buckle, “History of Civilization in England” Vol. 2, 1891)
"[…] geometry is the art of reasoning well from badly drawn figures; however, these figures, if they are not to deceive us, must satisfy certain conditions; the proportions may be grossly altered, but the relative positions of the different parts must not be upset." (Henri Poincaré, 1895)
"Geometry has been, throughout, of supreme importance in the history of knowledge." (Bertrand Russell, :Foundations of Geometry", 1897)
"[…] there are terms which cannot be defined, such as number and quantity. Any attempt at a definition would only throw difficulty in the student’s way, which is already done in geometry by the attempts at an explanation of the terms point, straight line, and others, which are to be found in treatise on that subject." (Augustus de Morgan, "On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics", 1898)
"Geometry, then, is the application of strict logic to those properties of space and figure which are self-evident, and which therefore cannot be disputed. But the rigor of this science is carried one step further; for no property, however evident it may be, is allowed to pass without demonstration, if that can be given. The question is therefore to demonstrate all geometrical truths with the smallest possible number of assumptions." (Augustus de Morgan, "On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics", 1898)
"The truth is that other systems of geometry are possible, yet after all, these other systems are not spaces but other methods of space measurements. There is one space only, though we may conceive of many different manifolds, which are contrivances or ideal constructions invented for the purpose of determining space." (Paul Carus, Science Vol. 18, 1903)
"We believe that in our reasonings we no longer appeal to intuition; the philosophers will tell us this is an illusion. Pure logic could never lead us to anything but tautologies; it could create nothing new; not from it alone can any science issue. In one sense these philosophers are right; to make arithmetic, as to make geometry, or to make any science, something else than pure logic is necessary. To designate this something else we have no word other than intuition. But how many different ideas are hidden under this same word?" (Henri Poincaré , "Intuition and Logic in Mathematics", 1905)
"Architecture is geometry made visible in the same sense that music is number made audible." (Claude F Bragdon, "The Beautiful Necessity: Seven Essays on Theosophy and Architecture", 1910)
"The ends to be attained [in mathematical teaching] are the knowledge of a body of geometrical truths to be used In the discovery of new truths, the power to draw correct inferences from given premises, the power to use algebraic processes as a means of finding results in practical problems, and the awakening of interest In the science of mathematics." (J Craig, "A Course of Study for the Preparation of Rural School Teachers", 1912)
"Geometers usually distinguish two kinds of geometry, the first of which they qualify as metric and the second as projective. Metric geometry is based on the notion of distance; two figures are there regarded as equivalent when they are 'congruent' in the sense that mathematicians give to this word. Projective geometry is based on the notion of straight line; in order for two figures considered there to be equivalent, it is not necessary that they be congruent; it suffices that one can pass from one to the other by a projective transformation, that is, that one be the perspective of the other. This second body of study has often been called qualitative geometry, and in fact it is if one opposes it to the first; it is clear that measure and quantity play a less important role. This is not entirely so, however. The fact that a line is straight is not purely qualitative; one cannot assure himself that a line is straight without making measurements, or without sliding on this line an instrument called a straightedge, which is a kind of instrument of measure.” (Henri Poincaré, “Dernières pensées”, 1913)
"Projective Geometry: a boundless domain of countless fields where reals and imaginaries, finites and infinites, enter on equal terms, where the spirit delights in the artistic balance and symmetric interplay of a kind of conceptual and logical counterpoint - an enchanted realm where thought is double and flows throughout in parallel streams." (Cassius J Keyser, "The Human Worth of Rigorous Thinking: Essays and Addresses", 1916)
"As the objects of abstract geometry cannot be totally grasped by space intuition, a rigorous proof in abstract geometry can never be based only on intuition, but it must be founded on logical deduction from valid and precise axioms." (Felix Klein, "Elementary Mathematics from a Higher Standpoint" 3rd Ed. Vol. 3, 1928)
"Any mathematical science is a body of theorems deduced from a set of axioms. A geometry is a mathematical science. The question then arises why the name geometry is given to some mathematical sciences and not to others. It is likely that there is no definite answer to this question, but that a branch of mathematics is called a geometry because the name seems good, on emotional and people." (John H C Whitehead, „The Foundation of Differential Geometry", 1932)
"Geometry, whatever others may think, is the study of different shapes, many of them very beautiful, having harmony, grace and symmetry. […] Most of us, if we can play chess at all, are content to play it on a board with wooden chess pieces; but there are some who play the game blindfolded and without touching the board. It might be a fair analogy to say that abstract geometry is like blindfold chess – it is a game played without concrete objects." (Edward Kasner & James R Newman, "New Names for Old", 1940)
"The main thing geometry gives us is the ideal of a logical system and of precise thinking, and some acquaintance with the language in which logical arguments are usually expressed. The answer to a problem in actual life can often be obtained by further investigation of the actual facts, while in geometry it can always be obtained by reasoning alone." (George D Birkhoff & Ralph Beately, "Basic Geometry", 1940)
"The majority of geometric relations cluster around the ideas ‘equal’ and ‘similar’. That is why the simplest notions about equal and similar triangles are taken as the basis of this geometry. From these simplest notions we derive the more complicated relations of geometry." (George D Birkhoff & Ralph Beately, "Basic Geometry", 1940)
"Geometry, then, is the application of strict logic to those properties of space and figure which are self-evident, and which therefore cannot be disputed. But the rigor of this science is carried one step further; for no property, however evident it may be, is allowed to pass without demonstration, if that can be given. The question is therefore to demonstrate all geometrical truths with the smallest possible number of assumptions." (Augustus de Morgan, "On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics", 1943)
"Geometrical truth is a product of reason; that makes it superior to empirical truth, which is found through generalization of a great number of instances." (Hans Reichenbach, "The Rise of Scientific Philosophy", 1954)
“[…] no branch of mathematics competes with projective geometry in originality of ideas, coordination of intuition in discovery and rigor in proof, purity of thought, logical finish, elegance of proofs and comprehensiveness of concepts. The science born of art proved to be an art.” (Morris Kline, “Projective Geometry”, Scientific America Vol. 192 (1), 1955)
"Conventionalism as geometrical and mathematical truths are created by our choices, not dictated by or imposed on us by scientific theory. The idea that geometrical truth is truth we create by the understanding of certain conventions in the discovery of non-Euclidean geometries." (Clifford Singer, "Engineering a Visual Field", 1955)
"If indeed one tries to clarify the notion of equality, which is introduced right at the beginning of Geometry, one is led to say that two figures are equal when one can go from one to the other by a specific geometric operation, called a motion. This is only a change of words; but the axiom according to which two figures equal to a third are equal to one another, subjects those operations called motions to a certain law; that is, that an operation which is the result of two successive motions is itself a motion. It is this law that mathematicians express by saying that motions form a group. Elementary Geometry can then be defined by the study of properties of figures which do not change under the operations of the group of motions." (Élie Cartan, "Notice sur les travaux scientifiques", 1974)
"[…] it is the whole logical structure of elementary Geometry which is contained in the group of motions and even, in a more precise manner, in the law according to which operations of that group compose with each other, independently of the nature of the objects on which these operations act. This law constitutes what we call the group structure." (Élie Cartan, "Notice sur les travaux scientifiques", 1974)
“Every branch of geometry can be defined as the study of properties that are unaltered when a specified figure is given specified symmetry transformations. Euclidian plane geometry, for instance, concerns the study of properties that are 'invariant' when a figure is moved about on the plane, rotated, mirror reflected, or uniformly expanded and contracted. Affine geometry studies properties that are invariant when a figure is 'stretched' in a certain way. Projective geometry studies properties invariant under projection. Topology deals with properties that remain unchanged even when a figure is radically distorted in a manner similar to the deformation of a figure made of rubber.” (Martin Gardner, "Aha! Insight", 1978)“Geometry is the study of shapes. Although true, this definition is so broad that it is almost meaningless. The judge of a beauty contest is, in a sense, a geometrician because he is judging […] shapes, but this is not quite what we want the word to mean. It has been said that a curved line is the most beautiful distance between two points. Even though this statement is about curves, a proper element of geometry, the assertion seems more to be in the domain of aesthetics rather than mathematics.” (Martin Gardner, "Aha! Insight", 1978)
"To enter a temple constructed wholly of invariable geometric proportions is to enter an abode of eternal truth." (Robert Lawlor, "Sacred Geometry", 1982)
"Geometry is the science of figures. We study various properties of figures, and classify given figures according to the results. We have the notion of invariants, which can serve as the most effective method of classification. We may briefly say that invariants describe geometric structures in terms of numbers." (Shigeyuki Morita, "Geometry of Differential Forms", 1997)
"Unfortunately, if we were to use geometry to explore the concept of the square root of a negative number, we would be setting a boundary to our imagination that would be difficult to cross. To represent -1 using geometry would require us to draw a square with each side length being less than zero. To be asked to draw a square with side length less than zero sounds similar to the Zen Buddhists asking ‘What is the sound of one hand clapping?’" (Les Evans, "Complex Numbers and Vectors", 2006)
"Geometrical truth is (as we now speak) synthetic: it states facts about the world. Such truths are not ordinary truths but essential truths, giving the reality of the empirical world in which they are imperfect embodied." (Fred Wilson, "The External World and Our Knowledge of It", 2008)
No comments:
Post a Comment