30 March 2022

Joscha Bach - Collected Quotes

"For all practical purposes, the universe is a pattern generator, and the mind 'makes sense' of these patterns by encoding them according to the regularities it can find. Thus, the representation of a concept in an intelligent system is not a pointer to a 'thing in reality', but a set of hierarchical constraints over (for instance perceptual) data." (Joscha Bach, "Seven Principles of Synthetic Intelligence", 2008)

"[...] motivation [...] does not arise from intelligence itself, but from a motivational system underlying all directed behavior." (Joscha Bach, "Seven Principles of Synthetic Intelligence", 2008)

"[…] the quality of a world model eventually does not amount to how 'truly' it depicts 'reality' , but how adequately it encodes the (sensory) patterns." (Joscha Bach, "Seven Principles of Synthetic Intelligence", 2008)

"Symbolic reasoning falls short not only in modeling low level behaviors but is also difficult to ground into real world interactions and to scale upon dynamic environments […] This has lead many […] to abandon symbolic systems […] and […]  focus on parallel distributed, entirely sub-symbolic approaches […] well suited for many learning and control tasks, but difficult to apply [in] areas such as reasoning and language." (Joscha Bach, "Principles of Synthetic Intelligence PSI: An Architecture of Motivated Cognition", 2009)

"The goal of building cognitive architectures is to achieve an understanding of mental processes by constructing testable information processing models." (Joscha Bach, "Principles of Synthetic Intelligence PSI: An Architecture of Motivated Cognition", 2009)

"Deep learning is about using a stacked hierarchy of feature detectors. [...] we use pattern detectors and we build them into networks that are arranged in hundreds of layers and then we adjust the links between these layers, usually using some kind of gradient descent." (Joscha Bach, "Joscha: Computational Meta-Psychology", 2015)

"For a long time people have thought that the universe is written in mathematics […] In fact nothing is mathematical. Mathematics is just the domain of formal languages. It doesn't exist. Mathematics starts with a void. Just throw in a few axioms and if those are nice axioms, then you get infinite complexity. Most of it is not computable. In mathematics you can express arbitrary statements, because it's all about formal languages. Many of these statements will not make sense. Many of these statements will make sense in some way, but you cannot test whether they make sense because they're not computable." (Joscha Bach, "Joscha: Computational Meta-Psychology", 2015)

"Mathematics is the domain of all formal languages, and allows the expression of arbitrary statements (most of which are uncomputable). Computation may be understood in terms of computational systems, for instance via defining states (which are sets of discernible differences, i.e. bits), and transition functions that let us derive new states." (Joscha Bach, "The Cortical Conductor Theory: Towards Addressing Consciousness in AI Models", 2017)

"Whereas mathematics is the realm of specification, computation is the realm of implementation; it captures all those systems that can actually be realized." (Joscha Bach, "The Cortical Conductor Theory: Towards Addressing Consciousness in AI Models", 2017)

"Computational systems are machines that can be described apriori and systematically, and implemented on every substrate that elicits the causal properties that are necessary to capture the respective states and transition functions." (Joscha Bach, "The Cortical Conductor Theory: Towards Addressing Consciousness in AI Models", 2017)

29 March 2022

Alexander Humez - Collected Quotes

"A sequence can be finite or infinite. One way of defining a finite sequence is to list every one of its terms. But to define an infinite sequence, the terms must be capable of being generated, in order, by some procedure with a predictable result for each place in the string." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"An infinite set is any set from which you can remove some members without reducing its size. In fact, we can start with an infinite set, remove an infinite set, and still have an infinite set left behind […]." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"Finite-state machines, fundamental to the automatic translation and interpretation of languages used by computer programmers, can accept a limited set of inputs, and as the name implies, allow only a limited number of states. […] When it receives an input item (a coin for the vending machine, a pitch for the baseball count), the finite-state machine chooses a subsequent state based on both the input and the current state." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"In mathematics, a function is a sort of converter: It converts a value to some other value. […] the mathematical definition of a continuous function requires that any small change in the input will result in a small change to the output." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"Like the noble gases (helium, neon, argon, krypton, xenon, and radon), primes exist in splendid isolation; conversely, any composite number is the product of a unique set of prime factors." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"'Randomness', too, is in the eye of the beholder." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"The four-color map theorem is an assertion about graph theory, which is the study of discrete points and the lines that connect them; each point is called a vertex and each line is called an edge." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"Why is it so important to find primes, or to show that a certain integer is one? A very practical application in cryptography rests on the fact that since it is extremely hard to factor very large numbers, a two-hundred-digit number that was the product of two primes could govern text encoding: It would be virtually impossible to guess what the two numbers were if you didn't know them in advance, and out of the question (save perhaps on a state-of-the-art supercomputer) to go at it by trial and error." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"Zero is the only number that is neither positive nor negative. As such, it represents a quantity: If three is the name we give to the number of items in a trilogy, a trinity, or a triad, zero is our name for the number of items in an empty, or null set, i.e., one having no members. This is not the same as saying the set doesn't exist; in fact, we can and do make valid assertions about null sets […]" (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

"Zero is where it all begins, the clean slate. We speak of zero-sum games (in which anyone who wins anything does so only at the equal expense of the losers), zero hour (the time at which a military operation begins), ground zero (the impact point of a bomb, particularly a nuclear one), to zero in on something (getting it precisely in the cross hairs), zero degrees of temperature-which, depending on the scale you use, can be the freezing point of water (Centigrade), fortified wine (Fahrenheit), or the universe (Kelvin); the last, a bit chillier than - 2730 C or - 459' F, is aptly called absolute zero." (Alexander Humez et al, "Zero to Lazy Eight: The romance of numbers", 1993)

28 March 2022

Ernst Zermelo - Collected Quotes

"As for me (and probably I am not alone in this opinion), I believe that a single universally valid principle summarizing an abundance of established experimental facts according to the rules of induction, is more reliable than a theory which by its nature can never be directly verified; so I prefer to give up the theory rather than the principle, if the two are incompatible." (Ernst Zermelo, "Über mechanische Erklärungen irreversibler Vorgänge. Eine Antwort auf Hrn. Boltzmann’s ‘Entgegnung’" Annalen der Physik und Chemie 59, 1896)

"It is not admissible to accept this property simply as a fact for the initial states that we can observe at present, for it is not a certain unique variable we have to deal with (as, for example, the eccentricity of the earth’s orbit which is just decreasing for a still very long time) but the entropy of any arbitrary system free of external influences. How does it happen, then, that in such a system there always occurs only an increase of entropy and equalization of temperature and concentration differences, but never the reverse? And to what extent are we justified in expecting that this behaviour will continue, at least for the immediate future? A satisfactory answer to these questions must be given in order to be allowed to speak of a truly mechanical analogue of the Second Law." (Ernst Zermelo, "Über mechanische Erklärungen irreversibler Vorgänge. Eine Antwort auf Hrn. Boltzmann’s ‘Entgegnung’" Annalen der Physik und Chemie 59, 1896)

"[...] the spirit of the mechanical view of nature itself which will always force us to assume that all imaginable mechanical initial states are physically possible, at least within certain boundaries." (Ernst Zermelo, "Über einen Satz der Dynamik und die mechanische Wärmetheorie", Annalen der Physik und Chemie 57, 1896)

"Banishing fundamental facts or problems from science merely because they cannot be dealt with by means of certain prescribed principles would be like forbidding the further extension of the theory of parallels in geometry because the axiom upon which this theory rests has been shown to be unprovable. Actually, principles must be judged from the point of view of science, and not science from the point of view of principles fixed once and for all." (Ernst Zermelo, "Neuer Beweis für die Möglichkeit einer Wohlordnung", Mathematische Annalen 65, 1908)

"Generally speaking, mathematical theorems are no analytic judgements yet, but we can reduce them to analytic ones through the hypothetical addition of synthetic premises. The logically reduced mathematical theorems emerging in this way are analytically hypothetical judgements which constitute the logical skeleton of a mathematical theory." (Ernst Zermelo, "Mathematische Logik. Vorlesungen gehalten von Prof. Dr. E. Zermelo zu Göttingen im S.S.", 1908)

"If one intends to base arithmetic on the theory of natural numbers as finite cardinals, one has to deal mainly with the definition of finite set; for the cardinal is, according to its nature, a property of a set, and any proposition about finite cardinals can always be expressed as a proposition about finite sets. In the following I will try to deduce the most important property of natural numbers, namely the principle of complete induction, from a definition of finite set which is as simple as possible, at the same time showing that the different definitions [of finite set] given so far are equivalent to the one given here." (Ernst Zermelo,  "Ueber die Grundlagen der Arithmetik", Atti del IV Congresso Internazionale dei Matematici, 1908)

"It has been argued that mathematics is not or, at least, not exclusively an end in itself; after all it should also be applied to reality. But how can this be done if mathematics consisted of definitions and analytic theorems deduced from them and we did not know whether these are valid in reality or not. One can argue here that of course one first has to convince oneself whether the axioms of a theory are valid in the area of reality to which the theory should be applied. In any case, such a statement requires a procedure which is outside logic.” (Ernst Zermelo, "Mathematische Logik - Vorlesungen gehalten von Prof. Dr. E. Zermelo zu Göttingen im S. S", 1908)

"Now even in mathematics unprovability, as is well known, is in no way equivalent to nonvalidity, since, after all, not everything can be proved, but every proof in turn presupposes unproved principles. Thus, in order to reject such a fundamental principle, one would have to ascertain that in some particular case it did not hold or to derive contradictory consequences from it; but none of my opponents has made any attempt to do this." (Ernst Zermelo, "Neuer Beweis für die Möglichkeit einer Wohlordnung", Mathematische Annalen 65, 1908)

26 March 2022

Samuel Eilenberg - Collected Quotes

"It should be observed first that the whole concept of a category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are essentially those of a functor and of a natural transformation […]. The idea of a category is required only by the precept that every function should have a definite class as domain and a definite class as range, for the categories are provided as the domains and ranges of functors. Thus one could drop the category concept altogether […]" (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The invariant character of a mathematical discipline can be formulated in these terms. Thus, in group theory all the basic constructions can be regarded as the definitions of co- or contravariant functors, so we may formulate the dictum: The subject of group theory is essentially the study of those constructions of groups which behave in a covariant or contravariant manner under induced homomorphisms." (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders MacLane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The subject of group theory is essentially the study of those constructions of groups which behave in a covariant or contravariant manner under induced homomorphisms. More precisely, group theory studies functors defined on well specified categories of groups, with values in another such category." (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The theory [of categories] also emphasizes that, whenever new abstract objects are constructed in a specified way out of given ones, it is advisable to regard the construction of the corresponding induced mappings on these new objects as an integral part of their definition. The pursuit of this program entails a simultaneous consideration of objects and their mappings (in our terminology, this means the consideration not of individual objects but of categories). This emphasis on the specification of the type of mappings employed gives more insight onto the degree of invariance of the various concepts involved." (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"Speaking roughly, a homology theory assigns groups to topological spaces and homomorphisms to continuous maps of one space into another. To each array of spaces and maps is assigned an array of groups and homomorphisms. In this way, a homology theory is an algebraic image of topology. The domain of a homology theory is the topologist’s field of study. Its range is the field of study of the algebraist. Topological problems are converted into algebraic problems." (Samuel Eilenberg & Norman E Steenrod, "Foundations of Algebraic Topology", 1952)

"The diagrams incorporate a large amount of information. Their use provides extensive savings in space and in mental effort. In the case of many theorems, the setting up of the correct diagram is the major part of the proof. We therefore urge that the reader stop at the end of each theorem and attempt to construct for himself the relevant diagram before examining the one which is given in the text. Once this is done, the subsequent demonstration can be followed more readily; in fact, the reader can usually supply it himself." (Samuel Eilenberg & Norman E Steenrod, "Foundations of Algebraic Topology", 1952)

"Topology is an elastic version of geometry that retains the idea of continuity but relaxes rigid metric notions of distance." (Samuel Eilenberg)

Category Theory I

"It should be observed first that the whole concept of a category is essentially an auxiliary one; our basic concepts are essentially those of a functor and of a natural transformation […]. The idea of a category is required only by the precept that every function should have a definite class as domain and a definite class as range, for the categories are provided as the domains and ranges of functors. Thus one could drop the category concept altogether […]" (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The subject of group theory is essentially the study of those constructions of groups which behave in a covariant or contravariant manner under induced homomorphisms. More precisely, group theory studies functors defined on well specified categories of groups, with values in another such category." (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The theory [of categories] also emphasizes that, whenever new abstract objects are constructed in a specified way out of given ones, it is advisable to regard the construction of the corresponding induced mappings on these new objects as an integral part of their definition. The pursuit of this program entails a simultaneous consideration of objects and their mappings (in our terminology, this means the consideration not of individual objects but of categories). This emphasis on the specification of the type of mappings employed gives more insight onto the degree of invariance of the various concepts involved." (Samuel Eilenberg & Saunders Mac Lane, "A general theory of natural equivalences", Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 58, 1945)

"The notion of an abstract group arises by consideration of the formal properties of one-to-one transformations of a set onto itself. Similarly, the notion of a category is obtained from the formal properties of the class of all transformations y : X → Y of any one set into another, or of continuous transformations of one topological space into another, or of homomorphisms, of one group into another, and so on." (Saunders Mac Lane, "Duality for groups", Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 56, 1950)

"Categorical algebra has developed in recent years as an effective method of organizing parts of mathematics. Typically, this sort of organization uses notions such as that of the category G of all groups. [...] This raises the problem of finding some axiomatization of set theory - or of some foundational discipline like set theory - which will be adequate and appropriate to realizing this intent. This problem may turn out to have revolutionary implications vis-`a-vis the accepted views of the role of set theory." (Saunders Mac Lane, "Categorical algebra and set-theoretic foundations", 1967)

"The point is simply that when explaining the general notion of structure and of particular kinds of structures such as groups, rings, categories, etc., we implicitly presume as understood the ideas of operation and collection." (Solomon Feferman, "Categorical foundations and foundations of category theory", 1975)

"[…] it would be technically possible to give a purely category-theoretic account of all mathematical notions expressible within axiomatic set theory, and so formally possible for category theory to serve as a foundation for mathematics insofar as axiomatic set theory does." (John L Bell, "Category theory and the foundations of mathematics", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32(4), 1981)

"It is a remarkable empirical fact that mathematics can be based on set theory. More precisely, all mathematical objects can be coded as sets (in the cumulative hierarchy built by transfinitely iterating the power set operation, starting with the empty set). And all their crucial properties can be proved from the axioms of set theory. (. . . ) At first sight, category theory seems to be an exception to this general phenomenon. It deals with objects, like the categories of sets, of groups etc. that are as big as the whole universe of sets and that therefore do not admit any evident coding as sets. Furthermore, category theory involves constructions, like the functor category, that lead from these large categories to even larger ones. Thus, category theory is not just another field whose set-theoretic foundation can be left as an exercise. An interaction between category theory and set theory arises because there is a real question: What is the appropriate set-theoretic foundation for category theory?" (Andreas Blass, "The interaction between category theory and set theory", 1983)

"What was clearly useful was the use of diagrams to prove certain results either in algebraic topology, homological algebra or algebraic geometry. It is clear that doing category theory, or simply applying category theory, implies manipulating diagrams: constructing the relevant diagrams, chasing arrows by going via various paths in diagrams and showing they are equal, etc. This practice suggests that diagram manipulation, or more generally diagrams, constitutes the natural syntax of category theory and the category-theoretic way of thinking. Thus, if one could develop a formal language based on diagrams and diagrams manipulation, one would have a natural syntactical framework for category theory. However, moving from the informal language of categories which includes diagrams and diagrammatic manipulations to a formal language based on diagrams and diagrammatic manipulations is not entirely obvious." (Jean-Pierre Marquis, "From a Geometrical Point of View: A Study of the History and Philosophy of Category Theory", 2009)

"Category theory has developed classically, beginning with definitions and axioms and proceeding to a long list of theorems. Category theory is not topology (and so will not be described here), but it can be used to understand some of the relationships that exist among classes of topological spaces. It can be used to bring unity to diversity. [...] the theory of categories is not complete, it may not be completable, but it is a step forward in understanding foundational questions in mathematics." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

24 March 2022

On Functions II: Homeomorphism

"From the point of view of general topology, homeomorphic spaces are the same. That is to say, the properties that interest us are those that, when true for one space, are true for all spaces homeomorphic to it." (Andrew H Wallace, "Differential Topology: First Steps", 1968)

"A manifold can be given by specifying the coordinate ranges of an atlas, the images in those coordinate ranges of the overlapping parts of the coordinate domains, and the coordinate transformations for each of those overlapping domains. When a manifold is specified in this way, a rather tricky condition on the specifications is needed to give the Hausdorff property, but otherwise the topology can be defined completely by simply requiring the coordinate maps to be homeomorphisms." (Richard L Bishop & Samuel I Goldberg, "Tensor Analysis on Manifolds", 1968)

"A surface is a topological space in which each point has a neighbourhood homeomorphic to the plane, ad for which any two distinct points possess disjoint neighbourhoods. […] The requirement that each point of the space should have a neighbourhood which is homeomorphic to the plane fits exactly our intuitive idea of what a surface should be. If we stand in it at some point (imagining a giant version of the surface in question) and look at the points very close to our feet we should be able to imagine that we are standing on a plane. The surface of the earth is a good example. Unless you belong to the Flat Earth Society you believe it to,be (topologically) a sphere, yet locally it looks distinctly planar. Think more carefully about this requirement: we ask that some neighbourhood of each point of our space be homeomorphic to the plane. We have then to treat this neighbourhood as a topological space in its own right. But this presents no difficulty; the neighbourhood is after all a subset of the given space and we can therefore supply it with the subspace topology." (Mark A Armstrong, "Basic Topology", 1979)

"Showing that two spaces are homeomorphic is a geometrical problem, involving the construction of a specific homeomorphism between them. The techniques used vary with the problem. […] Attempting to prove that two spaces are not homeomorphic to one another is a problem of an entirely different nature. We cannot possibly examine each function between the two spaces individually and check that it is not a homeomorphism. Instead we look for 'topological invariants' of spaces: an invariant may be a geometrical property of the space, a number like the Euler number defined for the space, or an algebraic system such as a group or a ring constructed from the space. The important thing is that the invariant be preserved by a homeomorphism- hence its name. If we suspect that two spaces are not homeomorphic, we may be able to confirm our suspicion by computing some suitable invariant and showing that we obtain different answers." (Mark A Armstrong, "Basic Topology", 1979)

"Topology has to do with those properties of a space which are left unchanged by the kind of transformation that we have called a topological equivalence or homeomorphism. But what sort of spaces interest us and what exactly do we mean by a 'space? The idea of a homeomorphism involves very strongly the notion of continuity [...]"  (Mark A Armstrong, "Basic Topology", 1979)

"Geometry and topology most often deal with geometrical figures, objects realized as a set of points in a Euclidean space (maybe of many dimensions). It is useful to view these objects not as rigid (solid) bodies, but as figures that admit continuous deformation preserving some qualitative properties of the object. Recall that the mapping of one object onto another is called continuous if it can be determined by means of continuous functions in a Cartesian coordinate system in space. The mapping of one figure onto another is called homeomorphism if it is continuous and one-to-one, i.e. establishes a one-to-one correspondence between points of both figures." (Anatolij Fomenko, "Visual Geometry and Topology", 1994)

"The concept of homeomorphism appears to be convenient for establishing those important properties of figures which remain unchanged under such deformations. These properties are sometimes referred to as topological, as distinguished from metrical, which are customarily associated with distances between points, angles between lines, edges of a figure, etc." (Anatolij Fomenko, "Visual Geometry and Topology", 1994)

"Topology studies the properties of geometrical objects that remain unchanged under transformations called homeomorphisms and deformations." (Victor V Prasolov, "Intuitive Topology", 1995)

"One of the basic tasks of topology is to learn to distinguish nonhomeomorphic figures. To this end one introduces the class of invariant quantities that do not change under homeomorphic transformations of a given figure. The study of the invariance of topological spaces is connected with the solution of a whole series of complex questions: Can one describe a class of invariants of a given manifold? Is there a set of integral invariants that fully characterizes the topological type of a manifold? and so forth." (Michael I Monastyrsky, "Riemann, Topology, and Physics", 1999)

"Two figures which can be transformed into one other by continuous deformations without cutting and pasting are called homeomorphic. […] The definition of a homeomorphism includes two conditions: continuous and one- to-one correspondence between the points of two figures. The relation between the two properties has fundamental significance for defining such a paramount concept as the dimension of space." (Michael I Monastyrsky, "Riemann, Topology, and Physics", 1999)

"Intuitively, two spaces that are homeomorphic have the same general shape in spite of possible deformations of distance and angle. Thus, if two spaces are not homeomorphic, they will tend to look distinctly different. Our job is to specify the difference. To do this rigorously, we need to define some property of topological spaces and show that the property is preserved under transformations by any homeomorphism. Then if one space has the property and the other one does not have the property, there is no way they can be homeomorphic." (Robert Messer & Philip Straffin, "Topology Now!", 2006)

"The definition of homeomorphism was motivated by the idea of preserving the general shape or configuration of a geometric figure. Since path components are significant characteristics of a space, it is certainly reasonable that a homeomorphism will preserve the decomposition of a space into path components. […] Suppose we are given two geometric figures that we suspect are not topologically equivalent. If both of the figures are path-connected, counting components will not distinguish the spaces. However, we might be able to remove a special subset of one of the figures and count the number of components of the remainder. If no comparable set can be removed from the other space to leave the same number of components, we will then know that the two spaces are not homeomorphic." (Robert Messer & Philip Straffin, "Topology Now!", 2006)

"The easiest way to show two figures are homeomorphic is often to construct an explicit homeomorphism between them. But what if two figures are not homeomorphic? Surely we cannot be expected to check every function between the sets and show that it is not a homeomorphism. One of the goals of the field of topology is to discover easier ways of detecting the differences between spaces that are not homeomorphic." (Robert Messer & Philip Straffin, "Topology Now!", 2006)

"A topological property is, therefore, any property that is preserved under the set of all homeomorphisms. […] Homeomorphisms generally fail to preserve distances between points, and they may even fail to preserve shapes." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"In each branch of mathematics it is essential to recognize when two structures are equivalent. For example two sets are equivalent, as far as set theory is concerned, if there exists a bijective function which maps one set onto the other. Two groups are equivalent, known as isomorphic, if there exists a a homomorphism of one to the other which is one-to-one and onto. Two topological spaces are equivalent, known as homeomorphic, if there exists a homeomorphism of one onto the other." (Sydney A Morris, "Topology without Tears", 2011)

23 March 2022

Alexander L Fradkov - Collected Quotes

"A great deal of the results in many areas of physics are presented in the form of conservation laws, stating that some quantities do not change during evolution of the system. However, the formulations in cybernetical physics are different. Since the results in cybernetical physics establish how the evolution of the system can be changed by control, they should be formulated as transformation laws, specifying the classes of changes in the evolution of the system attainable by control function from the given class, i.e., specifying the limits of control." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

"A typical control goal when controlling chaotic systems is to transform a chaotic trajectory into a periodic one. In terms of control theory it means stabilization of an unstable periodic orbit or equilibrium. A specific feature of this problem is the possibility of achieving the goal by means of an arbitrarily small control action. Other control goals like synchronization and chaotization can also be achieved by small control in many cases." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

"Chaotic system is a deterministic dynamical system exhibiting irregular, seemingly random behavior. Two trajectories of a chaotic system starting close to each other will diverge after some time (such an unstable behavior is often called 'sensitive dependence on initial conditions'). Mathematically, chaotic systems are characterized by local instability and global boundedness of the trajectories. Since local instability of a linear system implies unboundedness (infinite growth) of its solutions, chaotic system should be necessarily nonlinear, i.e., should be described by a nonlinear mathematical model." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

"Systematic usage of the methods of modern control theory to study physical systems is a key feature of a new research area in physics that may be called cybernetical physics. The subject of cybernetical physics is focused on studying physical systems by means of feedback interactions with the environment. Its methodology heavily relies on the design methods developed in cybernetics. However, the approach of cybernetical physics differs from the conventional use of feedback in control applications (e.g., robotics, mechatronics) aimed mainly at driving a system to a prespecified position or a given trajectory." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

"The methodology of feedback design is borrowed from cybernetics (control theory). It is based upon methods of controlled system model’s building, methods of system states and parameters estimation (identification), and methods of feedback synthesis. The models of controlled system used in cybernetics differ from conventional models of physics and mechanics in that they have explicitly specified inputs and outputs. Unlike conventional physics results, often formulated as conservation laws, the results of cybernetical physics are formulated in the form of transformation laws, establishing the possibilities and limits of changing properties of a physical system by means of control." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

"The term synchronization in scientific colloquial use means coordination or agreement in time of two or several processes or objects. For example, it may be coincidence or closeness of the observable variables for two or several systems. Synchronization may also manifest itself as correlated in time changes of some quantitative characteristics of the systems." (Alexander L Fradkov, "Cybernetical Physics: From Control of Chaos to Quantum Control", 2007)

22 March 2022

John Tabak - Collected Quotes

"A crucial difference between topology and geometry lies in the set of allowable transformations. In topology, the set of allowable transformations is much larger and conceptu￾ally much richer than is the set of Euclidean transformations. All Euclidean transformations are topological transformations, but most topological transformations are not Euclidean. Similarly, the sets of transformations that define other geometries are also topological transformations, but many topological transformations have no counterpart in these geometries. It is in this sense that topology is a generalization of geometry." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"A topological property is, therefore, any property that is preserved under the set of all homeomorphisms. […] Homeomorphisms generally fail to preserve distances between points, and they may even fail to preserve shapes." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Abstract formulations of simply stated concrete ideas are often the result of efforts to create idealized models of complex systems. The models are 'idealized' in the sense that they retain only the most fundamental properties of the original systems. The vocabulary is chosen to be as inclusive as possible so that research into the model reveals facts about a wide variety of similar systems. Unfortunately, it is often the case that over time the connection between a model and the systems on which it was based is lost, and the interested reader is faced with something that looks as if it were created to be deliberately complicated - deliberately confusing - but the original intention was just the opposite. Often, the model was devised to be simpler and more transparent than any of the systems on which it was based." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Although topology grew out of geometry - at least in the sense that it was initially concerned with sets of geometric points - it quickly evolved to include the study of sets for which no geometric representation is possible. This does not mean that topological results do not apply to geometric objects. They do. Instead, it means that topological results apply to a very wide class of mathematical objects, only some of which have a geometric interpretation." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"At first glance, sets are about as primitive a concept as can be imagined. The concept of a set, which is, after all, a collection of objects, might not appear to be a rich enough idea to support modern mathematics, but just the opposite proved to be true. The more that mathematicians studied sets, the more astonished they were at what they discovered, and astonished is the right word. The results that these mathematicians obtained were often controversial because they violated many common sense notions about equality and dimension." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Category theory has developed classically, beginning with definitions and axioms and proceeding to a long list of theorems. Category theory is not topology (and so will not be described here), but it can be used to understand some of the relationships that exist among classes of topological spaces. It can be used to bring unity to diversity. [...] the theory of categories is not complete, it may not be completable, but it is a step forward in understanding foundational questions in mathematics." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Contemporary mathematics is often extremely abstract, and the important questions with which mathematicians concern themselves can sometimes be difficult to describe to the interested nonspecialist." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Every mathematical model of a scientific or engineering phenomenon must be sophisticated enough to reflect those characteristics that are important to the researcher, and the resulting equations must also be simple enough to solve." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Excessive specialization could mean that discoveries in one discipline would have no value outside the discipline - or worse, discoveries in one branch of mathematics would remain within that branch because specialists in other branches of mathematics simply could not understand the discoveries and how they related to their own work." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Mathematical knowledge agglomerates. When progress is made, mathematical discoveries are published for all to see, and the new is added to the old. In mathematics, new knowledge does not replace old knowledge, it grows alongside it. This is different from the way science often progresses. In science, new discoveries often replace old ones." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Much of mathematics can be understood as “model building.” In some cases, this is obvious. Applied mathematicians, for example, routinely describe their work as mathematical modeling. […] They make certain assumptions about the system in which they are interested, and then they investigate the logical consequences of their assumptions. They are successful when their models are simple enough to solve but sophisticated enough to capture the essential characteristics of the systems in which they are interested. Some so-called pure mathematicians also build models. They examine many different mathematical systems and attempt to identify those properties that are important to their research. They isolate those properties by specifying them in a set of axioms, and then they investigate the logical consequences of the axioms." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Of all mathematical disciplines, algebra has changed the most. While earlier generations of geometers would recognize - if not immediately understand - much of modern geometry as an extension of the subject that they had studied, it is doubtful that earlier generations of algebraists would recognize most of modern algebra as in any way related to the subject to which they devoted their time." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"The details of the shapes of the neighborhoods are not important. If the two sets of neighborhoods satisfy the equivalence criterion, then any set that is open, closed, and so on with respect to one set of neighborhoods will be open, closed, and so on with respect to the other set of neighborhoods." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"The idea behind an inductive definition is to define a set of terms sequentially, usually beginning with a trivial case, and proceeding up the chain of terms. Each link in the chain is defined in terms of the preceding link." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"[…] topologies are determined by the way the neighborhoods are defined. Neighborhoods, not individual points, are what matter. They determine the topological structure of the parent set. In fact, in topology, the word point conveys very little information at all." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"What distinguishes topological transformations from geometric ones is that topological transformations are more 'primitive'. They retain only the most basic properties of the sets of points on which they act." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"While mathematicians now recognize that there is some freedom in the choice of the axioms one uses, not any set of statements can serve as a set of axioms. In particular, every set of axioms must be logically consistent, which is another way of saying that it should not be possible to prove a particular statement simultaneously true and false using the given set of axioms. Also, axioms should always be logically independent - that is, no axiom should be a logical consequence of the others. A statement that is a logical consequence of some of the axioms is a theorem, not an axiom." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

21 March 2022

On Inquiry VIII: Inquiry in Science III (1925-1949)

"[Philosophy] has tried to combine acceptance of the conclusions of scientific inquiry as to the natural world with the acceptance of doctrines about the nature of mind and knowledge which originated before there was such a thing as systematic experimental inquiry. Between the two there is an inherent incompatibility." (John Dewey, "Quest for Certainty: A Study of the Relation of Knowledge and Action", 1929)

"A Weltanschauung [worldview] is an intellectual construction which solves all the problems of our existence uniformly on the basis of one overriding hypothesis, which, accordingly, leaves no question unanswered and in which everything that interests us finds its fixed place [...] the worldview of science already departs noticeably from our definition. It is true that it too assumes the uniformity of the explanation of the universe; but it does so only as a programme, the fulfillment of which is relegated to the future." Sigmund Freud, "New introductory lectures on psycho-analysis", 1932)

"The formulation of a problem is often more essential than its solution, which may be merely a matter of mathematical or experimental skill. To raise new questions, new possibilities, to regard old problems from a new angle requires creative imagination and marks real advances in science." (Albert Einstein & Leopold Infeld, "The Evolution of Physics", 1938)

"Science is the organised attempt of mankind to discover how things work as causal systems. The scientific attitude of mind is an interest in such questions. It can be contrasted with other attitudes, which have different interests; for instance the magical, which attempts to make things work not as material systems but as immaterial forces which can be controlled by spells; or the religious, which is interested in the world as revealing the nature of God." (Conrad H Waddington, "The Scientific Attitude", 1941)

"Only by the analysis and interpretation of observations as they are made, and the examination of the larger implications of the results, is one in a satisfactory position to pose new experimental and theoretical questions of the greatest significance." (John A Wheeler, "Elementary Particle Physics", American Scientist, 1947)

"An experiment is a question which science poses to Nature, and a measurement is the recording of Nature’s answer." (Max Plank, "The Meaning and Limits of Exact Science", Science, 1949)

20 March 2022

On Inquiry XIX

"Discovery follows discovery, each both raising and answering questions, each ending a long search, and each providing the new instruments for a new search." (J Robert Oppenheimer, "Prospects in the Arts and Sciences", 1964)

"There are as many types of questions as components in the information." (Jacques Bertin, Semiology of graphics [Semiologie Graphique], 1967)

"Questions are the engines of intellect, the cerebral machines which convert energy to motion, and curiosity to controlled inquiry." (David H Fischer, "Historians’ Fallacies", 1970)

"Definitions, like questions and metaphors, are instruments for thinking. Their authority rests entirely on their usefulness, not their correctness. We use definitions in order to delineate problems we wish to investigate, or to further interests we wish to promote. In other words, we invent definitions and discard them as suits our purposes." (Neil Postman, "Language Education in a Knowledge Context", 1980)

"We make our world significant by the courage of our questions and by the depth of our answers." (Carl Sagan, "Cosmos", 1980)

"The purpose of models is not to fit the data but to sharpen the questions." (Samuel Karlin, 1983)

"Each of us carries within us a worldview, a set of assumptions about how the world works - what some call a paradigm - that forms the very questions we allow ourselves to ask, and determines our view of future possibilities." (Frances M Lappé, "Rediscovering America's Values", 1991)

"Patterns experienced again and again become intuitions. […] Intuitive judgments are made by our use of imagery; intuition is the result of mental model building. […] The mental model used and the form of the intuition is dependent upon the question being answered." (Roger Frantz, "Two Minds", 2005)

"It is also a good idea to not apply any given technique or method blindly, but to think ahead and see where one could hope such a technique to take one; this can allow one to save enormous amounts of time by eliminating unprofitable directions of inquiry before sinking lots of effort into them, and conversely to give the most promising directions priority."(Terence Tao, "Solving Mathematical Problems: A Personal Perspective", 2006)

"[...] we also distinguish knowledge from information, because some pieces of information, such as questions, orders, and absurdities do not constitute knowledge. And also because computers process information but, since they lack minds, they cannot be said to know anything." (Mario Bunge, "Matter and Mind: A Philosophical Inquiry", 2010)

"Meta-analytic thinking is the consideration of any result in relation to previous results on the same or similar questions, and awareness that combination with future results is likely to be valuable. Meta-analytic thinking is the application of estimation thinking to more than a single study. It prompts us to seek meta-analysis of previous related studies at the planning stage of research, then to report our results in a way that makes it easy to include them in future meta-analyses. Meta-analytic thinking is a type of estimation thinking, because it, too, focuses on estimates and uncertainty." (Geoff Cumming, "Understanding the New Statistics", 2012)

On Inquiry XXI (Unsourced)

"General impressions are never to be trusted. Unfortunately when they are of long standing they become fixed rules of life and assume a prescriptive right not to be questioned. Consequently those who are not accustomed to original inquiry entertain a hatred and horror of statistics. They cannot endure the idea of submitting sacred impressions to cold-blooded verification. But it is the triumph of scientific men to rise superior to such superstitions, to desire tests by which the value of beliefs may be ascertained, and to feel sufficiently masters of themselves to discard contemptuously whatever may be found untrue." (Sir Francis Galton) 

"Indeed, when in the course of a mathematical investigation we encounter a problem or conjecture a theorem, our minds will not rest until the problem is exhaustively solved and the theorem rigorously proved; or else, until we have found the reasons which made success impossible and, hence, failure unavoidable. Thus, the proofs of the impossibility of certain solutions plays a predominant role in modern mathematics; the search for an answer to such questions has often led to the discovery of newer and more fruitful fields of endeavour." (David Hilbert)

"Mathematical inquiry lifts the human mind into closer proximity with the divine than is attainable through any other medium." (Hermann Weyl)

"Most practical questions can be reduced to problems of largest and smallest magnitudes […] and it is only by solving these problems that we can satisfy the requirements of practice which always seeks the best, the most convenient." (Pafnuty L Chebyshev)

"Nature responds only to questions posed in mathematical language, because nature is the domain of measure and order." (Alexandre Koyré)

"[…] no human inquiry can be called science unless it pursues its path through mathematical exposition and demonstration." (Leonardo da Vinci)

"Science descends ever more deeply into the hidden recesses of things, but it must halt at a certain point when questions arise which cannot be settled by means of sense observations. At that point the scientist needs a light which is capable of revealing to him truth which entirely escapes his senses. This light is philosophy." (Pope Pius XII)

"[...] the sole object of science is the honor of the human spirit and that under this view a problem of numbers is worth as much as a problem on the system of the world." (Carl G J Jacobi [letter to Legendre])

On Inquiry XIV: Inquiry in Science VI (2000-)

"Modeling involves a style of scientific thinking in which the argument is structured by the model, but in which the application is achieved via a narrative prompted by an external fact, an imagined event or question to be answered." (Uskali Mäki, "Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction", 2002)

"As the frontiers of science are continually pushed back, and the distance between experimenter and the world widens, the intelligibility of the world demands the construction and manipulation of models. Scientific discourse is often used to convey the information from well-grounded models. Scientific thinking is inescapably modeling and intimately involved with inquiry. ls, is essential for revealing unobserved, but observable, events." (Daniel Rothbart [Ed.], "Modeling: Gateway to the Unknown", 2004)

"In sum, an enlightened understanding of both physical and social phenomena is possible through modeling, as various stages of inquiry. Just as real world models are inseparable from experiences of the empirical world, a narrative is thoroughly implicated in a social encounter. Actors resort to narratives as they respond to the movements of others and project possibilities for future encounters. An actor becomes a virtual witness to an idealized scene, drawing upon past encounters to construct a picture of future, hypothetical events." (Daniel Rothbart [Ed.], "Modeling: Gateway to the Unknown", 2004)

"It is clear today that modern science developed when people stopped debating metaphysical questions about the world and instead concerned themselves with the discovery of laws that were primarily mathematical." (Mordechai Ben-Ari, "Just a Theory: Exploring the Nature of Science", 2005)

"Historically, science has pursued a premise that Nature can be understood fully, its future predicted precisely, and its behavior controlled at will. However, emerging knowledge indicates that the nature of Earth and biological systems transcends the limits of science, questioning the premise of knowing, prediction, and control. This knowledge has led to the recognition that, for civilized human survival, technological society has to adapt to the constraints of these systems." (Nari Narasimhan, "Limitations of Science and Adapting to Nature", Environmental Research Letters, 2007)

"Economists are all too often preoccupied with petty mathematical problems of interest only to themselves. This obsession with mathematics is an easy way of acquiring the appearance of scientificity without having to answer the far more complex questions posed by the world we live in." (Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century, 2013)

"Science, at its core, is simply a method of practical logic that tests hypotheses against experience. Scientism, by contrast, is the worldview and value system that insists that the questions the scientific method can answer are the most important questions human beings can ask, and that the picture of the world yielded by science is a better approximation to reality than any other." (John M Greer, "After Progress: Reason and Religion at the End of the Industrial Age", 2015)

"Intellectual inquiry begins with myth, religion and philosophy. Originally, philosophy (or perhaps theology or metaphysics) is the queen of the sciences, other intellectual disciplines having only a highly subservient, specialized role to play within philosophy. [...] Instead of being the queen of the sciences, overarching all other sciences, philosophy has been transformed into a highly specialized, technical, somewhat meagre enterprise, concerned not with improving our knowledge and understanding of the world - for that is the business of the empirical sciences - but rather with clarifying concepts and solving conceptual problems." (Nicholas Maxwell, "Karl Popper, Science and Enlightenment", 2017)

On Inquiry V: Inquiry in Science II (1900-1924)

"The man of science deals with questions which commonly lie outside of the range of ordinary experience, which often have no immediately discernible relation to the affairs of everyday life, and which concentrate the mind upon apparent abstractions to an extraordinary degree." (Frank W Clarke, "The Man of Science in Practical Affairs", Appletons' Popular Science Monthly Vol. XLV, 1900)

"Scientific facts are of little value in themselves. Their significance is their bearing upon other facts, enabling us to generalize and so to discover principles, just as the accurate measurement of the position of a star may be without value in itself, but in relation to other similar measurement of other stars may become the means of discovering their proper motions. We refine our instruments; we render more trustworthy our means of observation we extend our range of experimental inquiry, and thus lay the foundation for the future work, with the full knowledge that, although our researches can not extend beyond certain limits, the field itself is, even within those limits, inexhaustible." (Elihu Thompson, "The Field of Experimental Research", 1901)

"It is a matter of primary importance in the cultivation of those sciences in which truth is discoverable by the human intellect that the investigator should be free, independent, unshackled in his movement; that he should be allowed and enabled to fix his mind intently, nay, exclusively, on his special object, without the risk of being distracted every other minute in the process and progress of his inquiry by charges of temerariousness, or by warnings against extravagance or scandal." (John H Newman, "The Idea of a University Defined and Illustrated", 1905)

"[...] the data with which any scientific inquiry has to do are trivialities in some other bearing than that one in which they are of account." (Thorstein Veblen, "The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation and Other Essays", 1906)

"Modern masters of science are much impressed with the need of beginning all inquiry with a fact. The ancient masters of religion were quite equally impressed with that necessity. They began with the fact of sin - a fact as practical as potatoes. Whether or not man could be washed in miraculous waters, there was no doubt at any rate that he wanted washing." (Gilbert K Chesterton, "Orthodoxy", 1908)

"The things to be investigated are either true or false. If false, pertinacious inquiry will reveal their falsity. If true, they are profoundly important. For there are no half-truths in Nature; every smallest departure has portentous consequences; our eyes must open slowly, or we should be overwhelmed." (Oliver J Lodge, "Raymond, or Life and Death", 1916)

"Scientific principles and laws do not lie on the surface of nature. They are hidden, and must be wrested from nature by an active and elaborate technique of inquiry." (John Dewey, "Reconstruction in Philosophy", 1920)

"The first distinguishing characteristic of thinking is facing the facts - inquiry, minute and extensive scrutinizing, observation." (John Dewey, "Reconstruction in Philosophy", 1920)

"The fundamental concepts of each science, the instruments with which it pro pounds its questions and formulates its solutions, are regarded no longer as passive images of something but as symbols created by the intellect itself." (Ernst Cassirer, "The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms", 1923)

On Inquiry XIII: Inquiry in Data Science III

 "To find signals in data, we must learn to reduce the noise - not just the noise that resides in the data, but also the noise that resides in us. It is nearly impossible for noisy minds to perceive anything but noise in data. […] Signals always point to something. In this sense, a signal is not a thing but a relationship. Data becomes useful knowledge of something that matters when it builds a bridge between a question and an answer. This connection is the signal." (Stephen Few, "Signal: Understanding What Matters in a World of Noise", 2015)

"[...] a data scientist role goes beyond the collection and reporting on data; it must involve looking at a business The role of a data scientist goes beyond the collection and reporting on data. application or process from multiple vantage points and determining what the main questions and follow-ups are, as well as recommending the most appropriate ways to employ the data at hand." (Jesús Rogel-Salazar, "Data Science and Analytics with Python", 2017)

"A data story starts out like any other story, with a beginning and a middle. However, the end should never be a fixed event, but rather a set of options or questions to trigger an action from the audience. Never forget that the goal of data storytelling is to encourage and energize critical thinking for business decisions." (James Richardson, 2017)

"A notable difference between many fields and data science is that in data science, if a customer has a wish, even an experienced data scientist may not know whether it’s possible. Whereas a software engineer usually knows what tasks software tools are capable of performing, and a biologist knows more or less what the laboratory can do, a data scientist who has not yet seen or worked with the relevant data is faced with a large amount of uncertainty, principally about what specific data is available and about how much evidence it can provide to answer any given question. Uncertainty is, again, a major factor in the data scientific process and should be kept at the forefront of your mind when talking with customers about their wishes."  (Brian Godsey, "Think Like a Data Scientist", 2017)

"In terms of characteristics, a data scientist has an inquisitive mind and is prepared to explore and ask questions, examine assumptions and analyse processes, test hypotheses and try out solutions and, based on evidence, communicate informed conclusions, recommendations and caveats to stakeholders and decision makers." (Jesús Rogel-Salazar, "Data Science and Analytics with Python", 2017)

"Again, classical statistics only summarizes data, so it does not provide even a language for asking [a counterfactual] question. Causal inference provides a notation and, more importantly, offers a solution. As with predicting the effect of interventions [...], in many cases we can emulate human retrospective thinking with an algorithm that takes what we know about the observed world and produces an answer about the counterfactual world." (Judea Pearl & Dana Mackenzie, "The Book of Why: The new science of cause and effect", 2018)

"Bayesian networks inhabit a world where all questions are reducible to probabilities, or (in the terminology of this chapter) degrees of association between variables; they could not ascend to the second or third rungs of the Ladder of Causation. Fortunately, they required only two slight twists to climb to the top." (Judea Pearl & Dana Mackenzie, "The Book of Why: The new science of cause and effect", 2018)

"Creating effective visualizations is hard. Not because a dataset requires an exotic and bespoke visual representation - for many problems, standard statistical charts will suffice. And not because creating a visualization requires coding expertise in an unfamiliar programming language [...]. Rather, creating effective visualizations is difficult because the problems that are best addressed by visualization are often complex and ill-formed. The task of figuring out what attributes of a dataset are important is often conflated with figuring out what type of visualization to use. Picking a chart type to represent specific attributes in a dataset is comparatively easy. Deciding on which data attributes will help answer a question, however, is a complex, poorly defined, and user-driven process that can require several rounds of visualization and exploration to resolve." (Danyel Fisher & Miriah Meyer, "Making Data Visual", 2018)

"[…] deep learning has succeeded primarily by showing that certain questions or tasks we thought were difficult are in fact not. It has not addressed the truly difficult questions that continue to prevent us from achieving humanlike AI." (Judea Pearl & Dana Mackenzie, "The Book of Why: The new science of cause and effect", 2018)

"Premature enumeration is an equal-opportunity blunder: the most numerate among us may be just as much at risk as those who find their heads spinning at the first mention of a fraction. Indeed, if you’re confident with numbers you may be more prone than most to slicing and dicing, correlating and regressing, normalizing and rebasing, effortlessly manipulating the numbers on the spreadsheet or in the statistical package - without ever realizing that you don’t fully understand what these abstract quantities refer to. Arguably this temptation lay at the root of the last financial crisis: the sophistication of mathematical risk models obscured the question of how, exactly, risks were being measured, and whether those measurements were something you’d really want to bet your global banking system on." (Tim Harford, "The Data Detective: Ten easy rules to make sense of statistics", 2020)

On Inquiry XII: Inquiry in Data Science II

"Modeling involves a style of scientific thinking in which the argument is structured by the model, but in which the application is achieved via a narrative prompted by an external fact, an imagined event or question to be answered." (Uskali Mäki, "Fact and Fiction in Economics: Models, Realism and Social Construction", 2002)

"Statistics depend on collecting information. If questions go unasked, or if they are asked in ways that limit responses, or if measures count some cases but exclude others, information goes ungathered, and missing numbers result. Nevertheless, choices regarding which data to collect and how to go about collecting the information are inevitable." (Joel Best, "More Damned Lies and Statistics: How numbers confuse public issues", 2004)

"The important thing is to understand that frequentist and Bayesian methods are answering different questions. To combine prior beliefs with data in a principled way, use Bayesian inference. To construct procedures with guaranteed long run performance, such as confidence intervals, use frequentist methods. Generally, Bayesian methods run into problems when the parameter space is high dimensional." (Larry A Wasserman, "All of Statistics: A concise course in statistical inference", 2004)

"Even in the best of circumstances, statistical analysis rarely unveils 'the truth'. We are usually building a circumstantial case based on imperfect data. As a result, there are numerous reasons that intellectually honest individuals may disagree about statistical results or their implications. At the most basic level, we may disagree on the question that is being answered." (Charles Wheelan, "Naked Statistics: Stripping the Dread from the Data", 2012)

"The four questions of data analysis are the questions of description, probability, inference, and homogeneity. [...] Descriptive statistics are built on the assumption that we can use a single value to characterize a single property for a single universe. […] Probability theory is focused on what happens to samples drawn from a known universe. If the data happen to come from different sources, then there are multiple universes with different probability models.  [...] Statistical inference assumes that you have a sample that is known to have come from one universe." (Donald J Wheeler," Myths About Data Analysis", International Lean & Six Sigma Conference, 2012)

"Don’t just do the calculations. Use common sense to see whether you are answering the correct question, the assumptions are reasonable, and the results are plausible. If a statistical argument doesn’t make sense, think about it carefully - you may discover that the argument is nonsense." (Gary Smith, "Standard Deviations", 2014)

"Mathematical modeling is the application of mathematics to describe real-world problems and investigating important questions that arise from it." (Sandip Banerjee, "Mathematical Modeling: Models, Analysis and Applications", 2014)

"The search for better numbers, like the quest for new technologies to improve our lives, is certainly worthwhile. But the belief that a few simple numbers, a few basic averages, can capture the multifaceted nature of national and global economic systems is a myth. Rather than seeking new simple numbers to replace our old simple numbers, we need to tap into both the power of our information age and our ability to construct our own maps of the world to answer the questions we need answering." (Zachary Karabell, "The Leading Indicators: A short history of the numbers that rule our world", 2014)

"We are seduced by patterns and we want explanations for these patterns. When we see a string of successes, we think that a hot hand has made success more likely. If we see a string of failures, we think a cold hand has made failure more likely. It is easy to dismiss such theories when they involve coin flips, but it is not so easy with humans. We surely have emotions and ailments that can cause our abilities to go up and down. The question is whether these fluctuations are important or trivial." (Gary Smith, "Standard Deviations", 2014)

"We don’t need new indicators that replace old simple numbers with new simple numbers. We need instead bespoke indicators, tailored to the specific needs and specific questions of governments, businesses, communities, and individuals." (Zachary Karabell, "The Leading Indicators: A short history of the numbers that rule our world", 2014)

On Inquiry XI: Inquiry in Data Science I

"There is no inquiry which is not finally reducible to a question of Numbers; for there is none which may not be conceived of as consisting in the determination of quantities by each other, according to certain relations." (Auguste Comte, "The Positive Philosophy", 1830)

"[...] the data with which any scientific inquiry has to do are trivialities in some other bearing than that one in which they are of account." (Thorstein Veblen, "The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation and Other Essays", 1906)

"The postulate of randomness thus resolves itself into the question, 'of what population is this a random sample?' which must frequently be asked by every practical statistician." (Ronald Fisher, "On the Mathematical Foundation of Theoretical Statistics", Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Vol. A222, 1922)

"Statistics are numerical statements of facts in any department of inquiry, placed in relation to each other; statistical methods are devices for abbreviating and classifying the statements and making clear the relations." (Arthur L Bowley, "An Elementary Manual of Statistics", 1934)

"Only by the analysis and interpretation of observations as they are made, and the examination of the larger implications of the results, is one in a satisfactory position to pose new experimental and theoretical questions of the greatest significance." (John A Wheeler, "Elementary Particle Physics", American Scientist, 1947)

"Errors of the third kind happen in conventional tests of differences of means, but they are usually not considered, although their existence is probably recognized. It seems to the author that there may be several reasons for this among which are 1) a preoccupation on the part of mathematical statisticians with the formal questions of acceptance and rejection of null hypotheses without adequate consideration of the implications of the error of the third kind for the practical experimenter, 2) the rarity with which an error of the third kind arises in the usual tests of significance." (Frederick Mosteller, "A k-Sample Slippage Test for an Extreme Population", The Annals of Mathematical Statistics 19, 1948)

"Almost any sort of inquiry that is general and not particular involves both sampling and measurement […]. Further, both the measurement and the sampling will be imperfect in almost every case. We can define away either imperfection in certain cases. But the resulting appearance of perfection is usually only an illusion." (Frederick Mosteller et al, "Principles of Sampling", Journal of the American Statistical Association Vol. 49 (265), 1954)

"The most important maxim for data analysis to heed, and one which many statisticians seem to have shunned is this: ‘Far better an approximate answer to the right question, which is often vague, than an exact answer to the wrong question, which can always be made precise.’ Data analysis must progress by approximate answers, at best, since its knowledge of what the problem really is will at best be approximate." (John W Tukey, "The Future of Data Analysis", Annals of Mathematical Statistics, Vol. 33, No. 1, 1962)

"At root what is needed for scientific inquiry is just receptivity to data, skill in reasoning, and yearning for truth. Admittedly, ingenuity can help too." (Willard v O Quine, "The Web of Belief", 1970)

"The purpose of models is not to fit the data but to sharpen the questions." (Samuel Karlin, 1983)

"Statistical models for data are never true. The question whether a model is true is irrelevant. A more appropriate question is whether we obtain the correct scientific conclusion if we pretend that the process under study behaves according to a particular statistical model." (Scott Zeger, "Statistical reasoning in epidemiology", American Journal of Epidemiology, 1991)

"[…] an honest exploratory study should indicate how many comparisons were made […] most experts agree that large numbers of comparisons will produce apparently statistically significant findings that are actually due to chance. The data torturer will act as if every positive result confirmed a major hypothesis. The honest investigator will limit the study to focused questions, all of which make biologic sense. The cautious reader should look at the number of ‘significant’ results in the context of how many comparisons were made." (James L Mills, "Data torturing", New England Journal of Medicine, 1993)

"Consideration needs to be given to the most appropriate data to be collected. Often the temptation is to collect too much data and not give appropriate attention to the most important. Filing cabinets and computer files world-wide are filled with data that have been collected because they may be of interest to someone in future. Most is never of interest to anyone and if it is, its existence is unknown to those seeking the information, who will set out to collect the data again, probably in a trial better designed for the purpose. In general, it is best to collect only the data required to answer the questions posed, when setting up the trial, and plan another trial for other data in the future, if necessary." (P Portmann & H Ketata, "Statistical Methods for Plant Variety Evaluation", 1997)

On Inquiry X: Inquiry in Science V (1975-1999)

"The mythology of science asserts that with many different scientists all asking their own questions and evaluating the answers independently, whatever personal bias creeps into their individual answers is canceled out when the large picture is put together." (Ruth Hubbard, "Women Look at Biology Looking at Women", 1979)

"The traditional boundaries between various fields of science are rapidly disappearing and what is more important science does not know any national borders. The scientists of the world are forming an invisible network with a very free flow of scientific information - a freedom accepted by the countries of the world irrespective of political systems or religions. […] Great care must be taken that the scientific network is utilized only for scientific purposes - if it gets involved in political questions it loses its special status and utility as a nonpolitical force for development." (Sune K. Bergström, [speech] 1982)

"[…] nature at the quantum level is not a machine that goes its inexorable way. Instead what answer we get depends on the question we put, the experiment we arrange, the registering device we choose. We are inescapably involved in bringing about that which appears to be happening." (John A Wheeler & Wojciech H Zurek, "Quantum Theory and Measurement", 1983)

"Computational reducibility may well be the exception rather than the rule: Most physical questions may be answerable only through irreducible amounts of computation. Those that concern idealized limits of infinite time, volume, or numerical precision can require arbitrarily long computations, and so be formally undecidable." (Stephen Wolfram, Undecidability and intractability in theoretical physics", Physical Review Letters 54 (8), 1985)

"Model building is the art of selecting those aspects of a process that are relevant to the question being asked. As with any art, this selection is guided by taste, elegance, and metaphor; it is a matter of induction, rather than deduction. High science depends on this art." (John H Holland," Hidden Order: How Adaptation Builds Complexity", 1995)

"Science is not a given set of answers but a system for obtaining answers. The method by which the search is conducted is more important than the nature of the solution. Questions need not be answered at all, or answers may be provided and then changed. It does not matter how often or how profoundly our view of the universe alters, as long as these changes take place in a way appropriate to science. For the practice of science, like the game of baseball, is covered by definite rules." (Robert Shapiro, "Origins: A Skeptic’s Guide to the Creation of Life on Earth", 1986)

"Even if there is only one possible unified theory, it is just a set of rules and equations. What is it that breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them to describe? The usual approach of science of constructing a mathematical model cannot answer the questions of why there should be a universe for the model to describe. Why does the universe go to all the bother of existing?" (Stephen W Hawking, "A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes", 1988)

"The usual approach of science of constructing a mathematical model cannot answer the questions of why there should be a universe for the model to describe. Why does the universe go to all the bother of existing?" (Stephen Hawking, "A Brief History of Time", 1988)

"It is part of the lore of science that the most parsimonious explanation of observed facts is to be preferred over convoluted and long-winded theories. Ptolemaic epicycles gave way to the Copernican system largely on this premise, and in general, scientific inquiry is governed by the oft-quoted dictum of the medieval cleric William of Occam that 'nunquam ponenda est pluralitas sine necesitate' , which may be paraphrased as 'choose the simplest explanation for the observed facts' ." (Edward Beltrami, "What is Random?: Chaos and Order in Mathematics and Life", 1999)

On Inquiry IX: Inquiry in Science IV (1950-1974)

"An experiment is a question which man asks of nature; one result of the observation is an answer which nature yields to man." (Ferdinand Gonseth, "The Primeval Atom", 1950)

"[…] the scientific picture of the real world around me is very deficient. It gives a lot of factual information, puts all our experience in a magnificently consistent order, but it is ghastly silent about all and sundry that is really near to our heart, that really matters to us. It cannot tell us a word about red and blue, bitter and sweet, physical pain and physical delight; it knows nothing of beautiful and ugly, good or bad, God and eternity. Science sometimes pretends to answer questions in these domains, but the answers are very often so silly that we are not inclined to take them seriously." (Erwin Schrödinger, "Nature and the Greeks", 1954)

"We have to remember that what we observe is not nature herself, but nature exposed to our method of questioning." (Werner K Heisenberg, "Physics and Philosophy: The revolution in modern science", 1958)

"Far better an approximate answer to the right question, which is often vague, than the exact answer to the wrong question, which can always be made precise." (John Tukey, "The Future of Data Analysis", Annals of Mathematical Statistics, Vol. 33, No. 1, 1962)

"We must accept, I think, that there is an inherent limitation in the structure of science that prevents a scientific theory from ever giving us an adequate total explanation of the universe. Always, there is a base in nature (or, correspondingly, a set of assumptions in theory) which cannot be explained by reference to some yet more fundamental property. This feature of science has been commented on by many writers in the philosophy of science; and, certainly the limitation is a point of difference between science and those religious or metaphysical systems in which there is an attempt to present a doctrine that gives answers for all ultimate questions." (Richard Schlegel, "Completeness in Science", 1967)

"The main role of models is not so much to explain and predict - though ultimately these are the main functions of science - as to polarize thinking and to pose sharp questions. Above all, they are fun to invent and to play with, and they have a peculiar life of their own. The 'survival of the fittest' applies to models even more than it does to living creatures. They should not, however, be allowed to multiply indiscriminately without real necessity or real purpose." (Mark Kac, "Some mathematical models in science" Science, Vol. 166 (3906), 1969)

"At root what is needed for scientific inquiry is just receptivity to data, skill in reasoning, and yearning for truth. Admittedly, ingenuity can help too." (Willard v O Quine, "The Web of Belief", 1970)

"The three attributes of commitment, imagination, and tenacity seem to be the distinguishing marks of greatness in a scientist. A scientist must be as utterly committed to the pursuit of truth as the most dedicated of mystics; he must be as pertinacious in his struggle to advance into uncharted country as the most indomitable pioneers; his imagination must be as vivid and ingenious as a poet’s or a painter’s. Like other men, for success he needs ability and some luck; his imagination may be sterile if he has not a flair for asking the right questions, questions to which nature’s reply is intelligible and significant." (Alfred M Taylor, "Imagination and the Growth of Science", 1970)

"Early scientific thinking was holistic, but speculative - the modern scientific temper reacted by being empirical, but atomistic. Neither is free from error, the former because it replaces factual inquiry with faith and insight, and the latter because it sacrifices coherence at the altar of facticity. We witness today another shift in ways of thinking: the shift toward rigorous but holistic theories. This means thinking in terms of facts and events in the context of wholes, forming integrated sets with their own properties and relationships."(Ervin László, "Introduction to Systems Philosophy", 1972)

On Inquiry VII: Inquiry in Mathematics III (2000-)

"Zero is powerful because it is infinity’s twin. They are equal and opposite, yin and yang. They are equally paradoxical and troubling. The biggest questions in science and religion are about nothingness and eternity, the void and the infinite, zero and infinity. The clashes over zero were the battles that shook the foundations of philosophy, of science, of mathematics, and of religion. Underneath every revolution lay a zero - and an infinity." (Charles Seife, "Zero: The Biography of a Dangerous Idea", 2000)

"While mathematical truth is the aim of inquiry, some falsehoods seem to realize this aim better than others; some truths better realize the aim than other truths and perhaps even some falsehoods realize the aim better than some truths do. The dichotomy of the class of propositions into truths and falsehoods should thus be supplemented with a more fine-grained ordering - one which classifies propositions according to their closeness to the truth, their degree of truth-likeness or verisimilitude. The problem of truth-likeness is to give an adequate account of the concept and to explore its logical properties and its applications to epistemology and methodology." (Graham Oddie, "Truth-likeness", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2001)

"Today, the whole subject of geometry extends way beyond the world of right-angled triangles, circles and so on. There are even branches of the subject in which the ideas of length, angle and area don’t really feature at all. One of these is topology – a sort of rubber-sheet geometry – where a recurring question is whether some geometric object can be deformed ‘smoothly’ into another one." (David Acheson, "1089 and All That: A Journey into Mathematics", 2002)

"A theorem is never arrived at in the way that logical thought would lead you to believe or that posterity thinks. It is usually much more accidental, some chance discovery in answer to some kind of question. Eventually you can rationalize it and say that this is how it fits. Discoveries never happen as neatly as that. You can rewrite history and make it look much more logical, but actually it happens quite differently." (Sir Michael Atiyah, 2004)

"It is clear today that modern science developed when people stopped debating metaphysical questions about the world and instead concerned themselves with the discovery of laws that were primarily mathematical." (Mordechai Ben-Ari, "Just a Theory: Exploring the Nature of Science", 2005)

"It is also a good idea to not apply any given technique or method blindly, but to think ahead and see where one could hope such a technique to take one; this can allow one to save enormous amounts of time by eliminating unprofitable directions of inquiry before sinking lots of effort into them, and conversely to give the most promising directions priority."(Terence Tao, "Solving Mathematical Problems: A Personal Perspective", 2006)

"There are three reasons for the study of inequalities: practical, theoretical and aesthetic. In many practical investigations, it is necessary to bound one quantity by another. The classical inequalities are very useful for this purpose. From the theoretical point of view, very simple questions give rise to entire theories. […] Finally, let us turn to the aesthetic aspects. As has been pointed out, beauty is in the eye of the beholder. However. it is generally agreed that certain pieces of music, art, or mathematics are beautiful. There is an elegance to inequalities that makes them very attractive." (Claudi Alsina & Roger B Nelsen, "When Less is More: Visualizing Basic Inequalities", 2009)

"Contemporary mathematics is often extremely abstract, and the important questions with which mathematicians concern themselves can sometimes be difficult to describe to the interested nonspecialist." (John Tabak, "Beyond Geometry: A new mathematics of space and form", 2011)

"Classification is only one of the mathematical aspects of catastrophe theory. Another is stability. The stable states of natural systems are the ones that we can observe over a longer period of time. But the stable states of a system, which can be described by potential functions and their singularities, can become unstable if the potentials are changed by perturbations. So stability problems in nature lead to mathematical questions concerning the stability of the potential functions." (Werner Sanns, "Catastrophe Theory" [Mathematics of Complexity and Dynamical Systems, 2012])

"Despite its deductive nature, mathematics yields its truths much like any other intellectual pursuit: someone asks a question or poses a challenge, others react or propose solutions, and gradually the edges of the debate are framed and a vocabulary is built." (David Perkins, "Calculus and Its Origins", 2012)

"Economists are all too often preoccupied with petty mathematical problems of interest only to themselves. This obsession with mathematics is an easy way of acquiring the appearance of scientificity without having to answer the far more complex questions posed by the world we live in." (Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century, 2013)

"Mathematical modeling is the application of mathematics to describe real-world problems and investigating important questions that arise from it." (Sandip Banerjee, "Mathematical Modeling: Models, Analysis and Applications", 2014)

"We tend to think of maths as being an 'exact' discipline, where answers are right or wrong. And it's true that there is a huge part of maths that is about exactness. But in everyday life, numerical answers are sometimes just the start of the debate. If we are trained to believe that every numerical question has a definite, 'right' answer then we miss the fact that numbers in the real world are a lot fuzzier than pure maths might suggest." (Rob Eastaway, "Maths on the Back of an Envelope", 2019)

On Inquiry VI: Inquiry in Mathematics II (1900-1999)

"The true mathematician is always a great deal of an artist, an architect, yes, of a poet. Beyond the real world, though perceptibly connected with it, mathematicians have created an ideal world which they attempt to develop into the most perfect of all worlds, and which is being explored in every direction. None has the faintest conception of this world except him who knows it; only presumptuous ignorance can assert that the mathematician moves in a narrow circle. The truth which he seeks is, to be sure, broadly considered, neither more nor less than consistency; but does not his mastership show, indeed, in this very limitation? To solve questions of this kind he passes unenviously over others." (Alfred Pringsheim, Jaresberichte der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung Vol 13, 1904)

"The infinite has always stirred the emotions of mankind more deeply than any other question; the infinite has stimulated and fertilized reason as few other ideas have; but also the infinite, more than any other notion, is in need of clarification." (David Hilbert, 1925)

"Mathematics has been called the science of the infinite. Indeed, the mathematician invents finite constructions by which questions are decided that by their very nature refer to the infinite. This is his glory." (Hermann Weyl, "Levels of Infinity", cca. 1930)

"The development of mathematics toward greater precision has led, as is well known, to the formalization of large tracts of it, so that one can prove any theorem using nothing but a few mechanical rules.[...] One might therefore conjecture that these axioms and rules of inference are sufficient to decide any mathematical question that can at all be formally expressed in these systems. It will be shown below that this is not the case, that on the contrary there are in the two systems mentioned relatively simple problems in the theory of integers that cannot be decided on the basis of the axioms." (Kurt Gödel, "On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems", 1931)

"But, despite their remoteness from sense experience, we do have something like a perception of the objects of set theory, as is seen from the fact that the axioms force themselves upon us as being true. I don't see any reason why we should have less confidence in this kind of perception, i.e., in mathematical intuition, than in sense perception, which induces us to build up physical theories and to expect that future sense perception will agree with them and, moreover, to believe that a question not decidable now has meaning and may be decided in future." (Kurt Gödel, "What is Cantor’s Continuum problem?", American Mathematical Monthly 54, 1947)

"The theory of numbers is particularly liable to the accusation that some of its problems are the wrong sort of questions to ask. I do not myself think the danger is serious; either a reasonable amount of concentration leads to new ideas or methods of obvious interest, or else one just leaves the problem alone. ‘Perfect numbers’ certainly never did any good, but then they never did any particular harm." (John E Littlewood, "A Mathematician’s Miscellany", 1953)

"There are at least four fundamental purposes that the study of mathematics should attain. First, it should serve as a functional tool in solving our individual everyday problems. These questions: How much? How many? What form or shape? and Can you prove it? arise every day in the lives of every citizen." (Howard F Fehr,  "Reorientation in Mathematics Education", Teachers Record 54, 1953) 

"The first [principle], is that a mathematical theory can only he developed axiomatically in a fruitful way when the student has already acquired some familiarity with the corresponding material - a familiarity gained by working long enough with it on a kind of experimental, or semiexperimental basis, i.e. with constant appeal to intuition. The other principle [...]  is that when logical inference is introduced in some mathematical question, it should always he presented with absolute honesty - that is, without trying to hide gaps or flaws in the argument; any other way, in my opinion, is worse than giving no proof at all." (Jean Dieudonné, "Thinking in School Mathematics", 1961)

"The most natural way to give an independence proof is to establish a model with the required properties. This is not the only way to proceed since one can attempt to deal directly and analyze the structure of proofs. However, such an approach to set theoretic questions is unnatural since all our intuition come from our belief in the natural, almost physical model of the mathematical universe." (Paul J Cohen, "Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis", 1966)

"[...] mathematics and poetry move together between two extremes of mysticism, the mysticism of the commonplace where ideas illuminate and create facts, and the mysticism of the extraordinary where God, the Infinite, the Real, poses the riddles of desire and disappointment, sin and salvation, effort and failure, question and paradoxical answer [...]" (Scott Buchanan, "Poetry and Mathematics", 1975)

"Don't just read it; fight it! Ask your own question, look for your own examples, dicover your own proofs. Is the hypothesis necessary? Is the converse true? What happens in the classical special case? What about the degenerate cases? Where does the proof use the hypothesis?" (Paul R Halmos, "I Want to be a Mathematician", 1985)

"One of the features that distinguishes applied mathematics is its interest in framing important questions about the observed world in a mathematical way. This process of translation into a mathematical form can give a better handle for certain problems than would be otherwise possible. We call this the modeling process. It combines formal reasoning with intuitive insights. Understanding the models devised by others is a first step in learning some of the skills involved, and that is how we proceed in this text, which is an informal introduction to the mathematics of dynamical systems." (Edward Beltrami, "Mathematics for Dynamic Modeling", 1987)

"The essence of modeling, as we see it, is that one begins with a nontrivial word problem about the world around us. We then grapple with the not always obvious problem of how it can be posed as a mathematical question. Emphasis is on the evolution of a roughly conceived idea into a more abstract but manageable form in which inessentials have been eliminated. One of the lessons learned is that there is no best model, only better ones."  (Edward Beltrami, "Mathematics for Dynamic Modeling", 1987)

"Even if there is only one possible unified theory, it is just a set of rules and equations. What is it that breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them to describe? The usual approach of science of constructing a mathematical model cannot answer the questions of why there should be a universe for the model to describe. Why does the universe go to all the bother of existing?" (Stephen W Hawking, "A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes", 1988)

"The usual approach of science of constructing a mathematical model cannot answer the questions of why there should be a universe for the model to describe. Why does the universe go to all the bother of existing?" (Stephen Hawking, "A Brief History of Time", 1988)

"[...] mystery is an inescapable ingredient of mathematics. Mathematics is full of unanswered questions, which far outnumber known theorems and results. It’s the nature of mathematics to pose more problems than it can solve. Indeed, mathematics itself may be built on small islands of truth comprising the pieces of mathematics that can be validated by relatively short proofs. All else is speculation." (Ivars Peterson, "Islands of Truth: A Mathematical Mystery Cruise", 1990)

"Mathematics is not a way of hanging numbers on things so that quantitative answers to ordinary questions can be obtained. It is a language that allows one to think about extraordinary questions." (James O Bullock, "Literacy in the Language of Mathematics", The American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 101, No. 8, October, 1994)

"Mathematics is not the study of an ideal, preexisting nontemporal reality. Neither is it a chess-like game with made-up symbols and formulas. Rather, it is the part of human studies which is capable of achieving a science-like consensus, capable of establishing reproducible results. The existence of the subject called mathematics is a fact, not a question. This fact means no more and no less than the existence of modes of reasoning and argument about ideas which are compelling an conclusive, ‘noncontroversial when once understood’." (Philip J Davis & Rueben Hersh, "The Mathematical Experience", 1995)

"Despite being partly familiar to all, because of these contradictory aspects, mathematics remains an enigma and a mystery at the heart of human culture. It is both the language of the everyday world of commercial life and that of an unseen and perfect virtual reality. It includes both free-ranging ethereal speculation and rock-hard certainty. How can this mystery be explained? How can it be unraveled? The philosophy of mathematics is meant to cast some light on this mystery: to explain the nature and character of mathematics. However this philosophy can be purely technical, a product of the academic love of technique expressed in the foundations of mathematics or in philosophical virtuosity. Too often the outcome of philosophical inquiry is to provide detailed answers to the how questions of mathematical certainty and existence, taking for granted the received ideology of mathematics, but with too little attention to the deeper why questions." (Paul Ernest, "Social Constructivism as a Philosophy of Mathematics", 1998)

"Rather mathematicians like to look for patterns, and the primes probably offer the ultimate challenge. When you look at a list of them stretching off to infinity, they look chaotic, like weeds growing through an expanse of grass representing all numbers. For centuries mathematicians have striven to find rhyme and reason amongst this jumble. Is there any music that we can hear in this random noise? Is there a fast way to spot that a particular number is prime? Once you have one prime, how much further must you count before you find the next one on the list? These are the sort of questions that have tantalized generations." (Marcus du Sautoy, "The Music of the Primes", 1998)

Related Posts Plugin for WordPress, Blogger...

On Data: Longitudinal Data

  "Longitudinal data sets are comprised of repeated observations of an outcome and a set of covariates for each of many subjects. One o...