Showing posts with label convergence. Show all posts
Showing posts with label convergence. Show all posts

20 October 2024

On Convergence IV

"Once more, an invariably-recurring lesson of geological history, at whatever point its study is taken up: the lesson of the almost infinite slowness of the modification of living forms. The lines of the pedigrees of living things break off almost before they begin to converge." (Thomas H Huxley, On the Formation of Coal, 1870)

"Analytic functions are those that can be represented by a power series, convergent within a certain region bounded by the so-called circle of convergence. Outside of this region the analytic function is not regarded as given a priori ; its continuation into wider regions remains a matter of special investigation and may give very different results, according to the particular case considered." (Felix Klein, "Sophus Lie", [lecture] 1893)

"Particular landforms or surface morphologies may be generated, in some cases, by several different processes, sets of environmental controls, or developmental histories. This convergence to similar forms despite variations in processes and controls is called equifinality." (Jonathan Phillips, "Simplexity and the Reinvention of Equifinality", Geographical Analysis Vol. 29 (1), 1997)

"The underlying reason for convergence seems to be that all organisms are under constant scrutiny of natural selection and are also subject to the constraints of the physical and chemical factors that severely limit the action of all inhabitants of the biosphere. Put simply, convergence shows that in a real world not all things are possible." (Simon C Morris, "The Crucible of Creation", 1998)

"Equifinality is the principle which states that morphology alone cannot be used to reconstruct the mode of origin of a landform on the grounds that identical landforms can be produced by a number of alternative processes, process assemblages or process histories. Different processes may lead to an apparent similarity in the forms produced. For example, sea-level change, tectonic uplift, climatic change, change in source of sediment or water or change in storage may all lead to river incision and a convergence of form." (Olav Slaymaker, "Equifinality", 2004)

"Convergence is, in my opinion, not only deeply fascinating but, curiously, it is as often overlooked. More importantly, it hints at the existence of a deeper structure to biology. It helps us to delineate a metaphorical map across which evolution must navigate. In this sense the Darwinian mechanisms and the organic substrate we call life are really a search engine to discover particular solutions, including intelligence and - risky thought - perhaps deeper realities?" (Simon C Morris,  "Aliens like us?", Astronomy and Geophysics Vol. 46 (4), 2005)

"Sometimes the most important fit statistic you can get is ‘convergence not met’ - it can tell you something is wrong with your model." (Oliver Schabenberger, "Applied Statistics in Agriculture Conference", 2006)

27 February 2022

On Convergence III (Trivia)

"It is the principle of necessity towards which, as to their ultimate centre, all the ideas advanced in this essay immediately converge. In abstract theory the limits of this necessity are determined solely by considerations of man’s proper nature as a human being; but in the application we have to regard, in addition, the individuality of man as he actually exists. This principle of necessity should, I think, prescribe the grand fundamental rule to which every effort to act on human beings and their manifold relations should be invariably conformed. For it is the only thing which conducts to certain and unquestionable results. The consideration of the useful, which might be opposed to it, does not admit of any true and unswerving decision." (Wilhelm Von Humboldt, "The Limits of State Action", 1792)

"The more man inquires into the laws which regulate the material universe, the more he is convinced that all its varied forms arise from the action of a few simple principles. These principles themselves converge, with accelerating force, towards some still more comprehensive law to which all matter seems to be submitted. Simple as that law may possibly be, it must be remembered that it is only one amongst an infinite number of simple laws: that each of these laws has consequences at least as extensive as the existing one, and therefore that the Creator who selected the present law must have foreseen the consequences of all other laws." (Charles Babbage, "Passages From the Life of a Philosopher", 1864)

"The more progress physical sciences makes, the more they tend to enter the domain of mathematics, which is a kind of center to which they all converge. We may even judge of the degree of perfection to which a science has arrived by the facility with which it may be submitted to calculation." (Adolphe Quetelet, "Annual Report of the Board of Regents of the Smithsonian Institution", 1874)

"Historical investigation not only promotes the understanding of that which now is, but also brings new possibilities before us, by showing that which exists to be in great measure conventional and accidental. From the higher point of view at which different paths of thought converge we may look about us with freer vision and discover routes before unknown." (Ernst Mach, "The Science of Mechanics", 1883)

"This is the reason why mechanical explanations are better understood than stories, even though they are more difficult to reproduce. The exposition, even if it is faulty, excites analogous schemas already existing in the listener’s mind; so that what takes place is not genuine understanding, but a convergence of acquired schemas of thought. In the case of stories, this convergence is not possible, and the schemas brought into play are usually divergent." (Jean Piaget, "The Language and Thought of the Child", 1926)

"No science has ever been born on a specific day. Each science emerges out of a convergence of an increased interest in some class of problems and the development of scientific methods, techniques, and tools which are adequate to solve these problems." (C West Churchman, "Introduction to Operations Research", 1957)

"Science, philosophy and religion are bound to converge as they draw nearer to the whole." (Pierre T de Chardin, "The Phenomenon of Man", 1959)

"Relativity is inherently convergent, though convergent toward a plurality of centers of abstract truths. Degrees of accuracy are only degrees of refinement and magnitude in no way affects the fundamental reliability, which refers, as directional or angular sense, toward centralized truths. Truth is a relationship." (R Buckminster Fuller, "The Designers and the Politicians", 1962)

"Knowledge is not a series of self-consistent theories that converges toward an ideal view; it is rather an ever increasing ocean of mutually incompatible (and perhaps even incommensurable) alternatives, each single theory, each fairy tale, each myth that is part of the collection forcing the others into greater articulation and all of them contributing, via this process of competition, to the development of our consciousness." (Paul K Feyerabend, "Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge", 1975)

"Today the world we see outside and the world we see within are converging. This convergence of two worlds is perhaps one of the important cultural events of our age." (Ilya Prigogine, "The Philosophy of Instability", Futures 21 (4), 1989)

"Scientists have discovered many peculiar things, and many beautiful things. But perhaps the most beautiful and the most peculiar thing that they have discovered is the pattern of science itself. Our scientific discoveries are not independent isolated facts; one scientific generalization finds its explanation in another, which is itself explained by yet another. By tracing these arrows of explanation back toward their source we have discovered a striking convergent pattern - perhaps the deepest thing we have yet learned about the universe." (Steven Weinberg, "Dreams of a Final Theory: The Scientist’s Search for the Ultimate Laws of Nature", 1992)

"A great discovery is not a terminus, but an avenue leading to regions hitherto unknown. We climb to the top of the peak and find that it reveals to us another higher than any we have yet seen, and so it goes on. The additions to our knowledge of physics made in a generation do not get smaller or less fundamental or less revolutionary, as one generation succeeds another. The sum of our knowledge is not like what mathematicians call a convergent series […] where the study of a few terms may give the general properties of the whole. Physics corresponds rather to the other type of series called divergent, where the terms which are added one after another do not get smaller and smaller, and where the conclusions we draw from the few terms we know, cannot be trusted to be those we should draw if further knowledge were at our disposal." (Sir Joseph J Thomson) 

On Convergence II (Systems)

"The system becomes more coherent as it is further extended. The elements which we require for explaining a new class of facts are already contained in our system. Different members of the theory run together, and we have thus a constant convergence to unity. In false theories, the contrary is the case." (William Whewell, "Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences", 1840)

"The power and beauty of stochastic approximation theory is that it provides simple, easy to implement gain sequences which guarantee convergence without depending (explicitly) on knowledge of the function to be minimized or the noise properties. Unfortunately, convergence is usually extremely slow. This is to be expected, as 'good performance' cannot be expected if no (or very little) knowledge of the nature of the problem is built into the algorithm. In other words, the strength of stochastic approximation (simplicity, little a priori knowledge) is also its weakness." (Fred C Scweppe, "Uncertain dynamic systems", 1973)

"When loops are present, the network is no longer singly connected and local propagation schemes will invariably run into trouble. [...] If we ignore the existence of loops and permit the nodes to continue communicating with each other as if the network were singly connected, messages may circulate indefinitely around the loops and process may not converges to a stable equilibrium. […] Such oscillations do not normally occur in probabilistic networks […] which tend to bring all messages to some stable equilibrium as time goes on. However, this asymptotic equilibrium is not coherent, in the sense that it does not represent the posterior probabilities of all nodes of the network." (Judea Pearl, "Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference", 1988)

"Regarding stability, the state trajectories of a system tend to equilibrium. In the simplest case they converge to one point (or different points from different initial states), more commonly to one (or several, according to initial state) fixed point or limit cycle(s) or even torus(es) of characteristic equilibrial behaviour. All this is, in a rigorous sense, contingent upon describing a potential, as a special summation of the multitude of forces acting upon the state in question, and finding the fixed points, cycles, etc., to be minima of the potential function. It is often more convenient to use the equivalent jargon of 'attractors' so that the state of a system is 'attracted' to an equilibrial behaviour. In any case, once in equilibrial conditions, the system returns to its limit, equilibrial behaviour after small, arbitrary, and random perturbations." (Gordon Pask, "Different Kinds of Cybernetics", 1992)

"Systems, acting dynamically, produce (and incidentally, reproduce) their own boundaries, as structures which are complementary (necessarily so) to their motion and dynamics. They are liable, for all that, to instabilities chaos, as commonly interpreted of chaotic form, where nowadays, is remote from the random. Chaos is a peculiar situation in which the trajectories of a system, taken in the traditional sense, fail to converge as they approach their limit cycles or 'attractors' or 'equilibria'. Instead, they diverge, due to an increase, of indefinite magnitude, in amplification or gain." (Gordon Pask, "Different Kinds of Cybernetics", 1992)

"The description of the evolutionary trajectory of dynamical systems as irreversible, periodically chaotic, and strongly nonlinear fits certain features of the historical development of human societies. But the description of evolutionary processes, whether in nature or in history, has additional elements. These elements include such factors as the convergence of existing systems on progressively higher organizational levels, the increasingly efficient exploitation by systems of the sources of free energy in their environment, and the complexification of systems structure in states progressively further removed from thermodynamic equilibrium." (Ervin László et al, "The Evolution of Cognitive Maps: New Paradigms for the Twenty-first Century", 1993) 

On Convergence I

"To the thought of considering the infinitely great not merely in the form of what grows without limits - and in the closely related form of the convergent infinite series first introduced in the seventeenth century-, but also fixing it mathematically by numbers in the determinate form of the completed-infinite, I have been logically compelled in the course of scientific exertions and attempts which have lasted many years, almost against my will, for it contradicts traditions which had become precious to me; and therefore I believe that no arguments can be made good against it which I would not know how to meet." (Georg Cantor, "Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre", 1883)

"Between mathematicians and astronomers some misunderstanding exists with respect to the meaning of the term 'convergence'. Mathematicians [...] stipulate that a series is convergent if the sum of the terms tends to a predetermined limit even if the first terms decrease very slowly. Conversely, astronomers are in the habit of saying that a series converges whenever the first twenty terms, for example, decrease rapidly even if the following terms might increase indefinitely. [...] Both rules are legitimate; the first for theoretical research and the second for numerical applications. Both must prevail, but in two entirely separate domains of which the boundaries must be accurately defined. Astronomers do not always know these boundaries accurately but rarely exceed them; the approximation with which they are satisfied usually keeps them far on this side of the boundary. In addition, their instinct guides them and, if they are wrong, a check on the actual observation promptly reveals their error [...]" (Henri Poincaré, "New Methods in Celestial Mechanics" ["Les méthodes nouvelles de la mécanique céleste"], 1892)

"Incidentally, naive intuition, which is in large part an inherited talent, emerges unconsciously from the in-depth study of this or that field of science. The word ‘Anschauung’ has not perhaps been suitably chosen. I would like to include here the motoric sensation with which an engineer assesses the distribution of forces in something he is designing, and even that vague feeling possessed by the experienced number cruncher about the convergence of infinite processes with which he is confronted. I am saying that, in its fields of application, mathematical intuition understood in this way rushes ahead of logical thinking and in each moment has a wider scope than the latter " (Felix Klein, "Über Arithmetisierung der Mathematik", Zeitschrift für mathematischen und naturwissen-schaftlichen Unterricht 27, 1896)

"The method of successive approximations is often applied to proving existence of solutions to various classes of functional equations; moreover, the proof of convergence of these approximations leans on the fact that the equation under study may be majorised by another equation of a simple kind. Similar proofs may be encountered in the theory of infinitely many simultaneous linear equations and in the theory of integral and differential equations. Consideration of semiordered spaces and operations between them enables us to easily develop a complete theory of such functional equations in abstract form." (Leonid V Kantorovich, "On one class of functional equations", 1936)

"Mathematics has, of course, given the solution of the difficulties in terms of the abstract concept of converging infinite series. In a certain metaphysical sense this notion of convergence does not answer Zeno’s argument, in that it does not tell how one is to picture an infinite number of magnitudes as together making up only a finite magnitude; that is, it does not give an intuitively clear and satisfying picture, in terms of sense experience, of the relation subsisting between the infinite series and the limit of this series." (Carl B Boyer, "The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development", 1959)

"Central to the development of the calculus were the concepts of convergence and limit, and with these concepts at hand it became at last possible to resolve the ancient paradoxes of infinity which had so much intrigued Zeno." (Eli Maor, "To Infinity and Beyond: A Cultural History of the Infinite", 1987)

"If we know when a sequence approaches a point or, as we say, converges to a point, we can define a continuous mapping from one metric space to another by using the property that a converging sequence is mapped to the corresponding converging sequence." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"[...] the only characteristic property that continuous functions have is that near objects are sent to corresponding near objects, that is, a convergent sequence is mapped to the corresponding convergent sequence. It is reasonable to say that we cannot expect to extract from that property neither numerical consequences, nor a method to extensively study continuity. On the contrary, analytic functions can be represented by equations (precisely speaking, by infinite series). Compared to analytic functions, continuous functions, in general, are difficult to represent explicitly, although they exist as a concept." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"Intuitively speaking, a visual representation associated with the concept of continuity is the property that a near object is sent to a corresponding near object, that is, a convergent sequence is sent to a corresponding convergent sequence." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"Theoretically, the normal distribution is most famous because many distributions converge to it, if you sample from them enough times and average the results. This applies to the binomial distribution, Poisson distribution and pretty much any other distribution you’re likely to encounter (technically, any one for which the mean and standard deviation are finite)." (Field Cady, "The Data Science Handbook", 2017)

"At the basis of the distance concept lies, for example, the concept of convergent point sequence and their defined limits, and one can, by choosing these ideas as those fundamental to point set theory, eliminate the notions of distance." (Felix Hausdorff)

25 January 2021

On Continuity I (Calculus)

"Since [...] nature is a principle of motion and mutation [...] it is necessary that we should not be ignorant of what motion is [...] But motion appears to belong to things continuous; and the infinite first presents itself to the view in that which is continuous. [..] frequently [...] those who define the continuous, employ the nature or the infinite, as if that which is divisible to infinity is continuous." (Aristotle, "Physics", cca. 350 BC)

"Things [...] are some of them continuous [...] which are properly and peculiarly called 'magnitudes'; others are discontinuous, in a side-by-side arrangement, and, as it were, in heaps, which are called 'multitudes,' a flock, for instance, a people, a heap, a chorus, and the like. Wisdom, then, must be considered to be the knowledge of these two forms. Since, however, all multitude and magnitude are by their own nature of necessity infinite - for multitude starts from a definite root and never ceases increasing; and magnitude, when division beginning with a limited whole is carried on, cannot bring the dividing process to an end [...] and since sciences are always sciences of limited things, and never of infinites, it is accordingly evident that a science dealing with magnitude [...] or with multitude [...] could never be formulated. […] A science, however, would arise to deal with something separated from each of them, with quantity, set off from multitude, and size, set off from magnitude." (Nicomachus, cca. 100 AD) 

"Since the nature of differentials […] consists in their being infinitely small and infinitely changeable up to zero, in being only quantitates evanescentes, evanescentia divisibilia, they will be always smaller than any given quantity whatsoever. In fact, some difference which one can assign between two magnitudes which only differ by a differential, the continuous and imperceptible variability of that infinitely small differential, even at the very point of becoming zero, always allows one to find a quantity less than the proposed difference." (Johann Bernoulli, cca. 1692–1702)

"There are two famous labyrinths where our reason very often goes astray. One concerns the great question of the free and the necessary, above all in the production and the origin of Evil. The other consists in the discussion of continuity, and of the indivisibles which appear to be the elements thereof, and where the consideration of the infinite must enter in." (Gottfried W Leibniz, "Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God and Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil", 1710)

"Every quantity which, keeping the same expression, increases or diminishes continually (non per saltum), is called a variable, and that which, with the same expression, keeps the same value, is called fixed or constant." (Pierre Varignon, "Eclaircissemens sur l'Analyse des Infinimens Petits", 1725)

"In fact, a similar principle of hardness cannot exist; it is a chimera which offends that general law which nature constantly observes in all its operations; I speak of that immutable and perpetual order, established since the creation of the Universe, that can be called the LAW OF CONTINUITY, by virtue of which everything that takes place, takes place by infinitely small degrees. It seems that common sense dictates that no change can take place at a jump; natura non operatur per saltion; nothing can pass from one extreme to the other without passing through all the degrees in between." (Johann Bernoulli, "Discours sur les Loix de la Communication du Mouvement", 1727)

"The Law of Continuity, as we here deal with it, consists in the idea that [...] any quantity, in passing from one magnitude to another, must pass through all intermediate magnitudes of the same class. The same notion is also commonly expressed by saying that the passage is made by intermediate stages or steps; [...] the idea should be interpreted as follows: single states correspond to single instants of time, but increments or decrements only to small areas of continuous time." (Roger J Boscovich, "Philosophiae Naturalis Theoria Redacta Ad Unicam Legera Virium in Natura Existentium", 1758)

"Any change involves at least two conditions, one preceding and one following, which are distinct from one another in such a way that the difference between the former and the latter can be established. Now the law of continuity prohibits the thing which is being changed to transcend abruptly from the former to the latter. It must pass through an intermediate condition which is as little distinct from the previous as from the subsequent one. And because the difference between this intermediate condition and the previous condition can be established still, there must be an intermediate condition between these two as well, and this must continue in the same way, until the difference between the previous condition and the one immediately succeeding it vanishes. As long as the set of these intermediate conditions can be established, every difference between one and the next can be established as well: hence their set must become larger than any given set if these differences shall vanish, and thus we imagine infinitely many conditions where one differs from the next to an infinitely small degree." (Abraham G Kästner, "Anfangsgründe der Analysis des Unendlichen" [Beginnings of the Analysis of the Infinite"], 1766)

"It is held because of this law in particular, that no change may occur suddenly, but rather that every change always passes by infinitely small stages, of which the trajectory of a point in a curved line provides a first example." (Abraham G Kästner, "Anfangsgründe der Analysis des Unendlichen" ["Beginnings of the Analysis of the Infinite"], 1766)

"Whoever wishes to extend this law [of continuity] to the real must justify his inferences by a law other than that, the suspicion remaining that he took images for things." (Abraham G Kästner, "Anfangsgründe der Analysis des Unendlichen" ["Beginnings of the Analysis of the Infinite"], 1766)

"[continuity] could be only appearance, and in this case Euler’s entire argument against the atoms would disappear; for one would be justified to apply the law of continuity only where experience shows that it agrees with the phenomena. [...]. The law of continuity thus belongs to the clothes of things which we must need rely on wherever reality seems impenetrably cloaked with it, but which we do not consider to be reality itself, and which we may still less cloak with things which do not serve us to see them." (Johann S T Gehler, "Physikalisches Wörterbuch" Bd. 4, 1798)

"Logic sometimes makes monsters. For half a century we have seen a mass of bizarre functions which appear to be forced to resemble as little as possible honest functions which serve some purpose. More of continuity, or less of continuity, more derivatives, and so forth. Indeed, from the point of view of logic, these strange functions are the most general; on the other hand those which one meets without searching for them, and which follow simple laws appear as a particular case which does not amount to more than a small corner. In former times when one invented a new function it was for a practical purpose; today one invents them purposely to show up defects in the reasoning of our fathers and one will deduce from them only that. If logic were the sole guide of the teacher, it would be necessary to begin with the most general functions, that is to say with the most bizarre. It is the beginner that would have to be set grappling with this teratologic museum." (Henri Poincaré, 1899)

"The Calculus required continuity, and continuity was supposed to require the infinitely little; but nobody could discover what the infinitely little might be." (Bertrand Russell, "Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays", cca. 1910)

"The course of the values of a continuous function is determined at all points of an interval, if only it is determined for all rational points of this interval." (Felix Klein, "Elementary Mathematics from a Higher Standpoint" Vol III: "Precision Mathematics and Approximation Mathematics", 1928)

"A common and very powerful constraint is that of continuity. It is a constraint because whereas the function that changes arbitrarily can undergo any change, the continuous function can change, at each step, only to a neighbouring value." (W Ross Ashby, "An Introduction to Cybernetics", 1956)

"As a simple trick, the discrete can often be carried over into the continuous, in a way suitable for practical purposes, by making a graph of the discrete, with the values shown as separate points. It is then easy to see the form that the changes will take if the points were to become infinitely numerous and close together." (W Ross Ashby, "An Introduction to Cybernetics", 1956)

"The mathematical theory of continuity is based, not on intuition, but on the logically developed theories of number and sets of points." (Carl B Boyer, "The History of the Calculus and Its Conceptual Development", 1959)

"Analysis is primarily concerned with limit processes and continuity, so it is not surprising that mathematicians thinking along these lines soon found themselves studying (and generalizing) two elementary concepts: that of a convergent sequence of real or complex numbers, and that of a continuous function of a real or complex variable." (George F Simmons, "Introduction to Topology and Modern Analysis", 1963)

"Continuous functions can move freely. Graphs of continuous functions can freely branch off at any place, whereas analytic functions coinciding in some neighborhood of a point P cannot branch outside of this neighborhood. Because of this property, continuous functions can mathematically represent wildly changing wind inside a typhoon or a gentle breeze." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"If we know when a sequence approaches a point or, as we say, converges to a point, we can define a continuous mapping from one metric space to another by using the property that a converging sequence is mapped to the corresponding converging sequence." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"Intuitively speaking, a visual representation associated with the concept of continuity is the property that a near object is sent to a corresponding near object, that is, a convergent sequence is sent to a corresponding convergent sequence." (Kenji Ueno & Toshikazu Sunada, "A Mathematical Gift, III: The Interplay Between Topology, Functions, Geometry, and Algebra", Mathematical World Vol. 23, 1996)

"If you assume continuity, you can open the well-stocked mathematical toolkit of continuous functions and differential equations, the saws and hammers of engineering and physics for the past two centuries (and the foreseeable future)." (Benoît Mandelbrot, "The (Mis)Behaviour of Markets: A Fractal View of Risk, Ruin and Reward", 2004)

"Continuity is the rigorous formulation of the intuitive concept of a function that varies with no abrupt breaks or jumps. A function is a relationship in which every value of an independent variable - say x - is associated with a value of a dependent variable - say y. Continuity of a function is sometimes expressed by saying that if the x-values are close together, then the y-values of the function will also be close. But if the question 'How close?' is asked, difficulties arise." (Erik Gregersen [Ed.], "Math Eplained: The Britannica Guide to Analysis and Calculus", 2011)

30 November 2020

Set Theory I

"[a set is] an embodiment of the idea or concept which we conceive when we regard the arrangement of its parts as a matter of indifference." (Bernard Bolzano, 1847)

"Since the examination of consistency is a task that cannot be avoided, it appears necessary to axiomatize logic itself and to prove that number theory and set theory are only parts of logic. This method was prepared long ago (not least by Frege’s profound investigations); it has been most successfully explained by the acute mathematician and logician Russell. One could regard the completion of this magnificent Russellian enterprise of the axiomatization of logic as the crowning achievement of the work of axiomatization as a whole." (David Hilbert, "Axiomatisches Denken" ["Axiomatic Thinking"], [address] 1917)

"It seems clear that [set theory] violates against the essence of the continuum, which, by its very nature, cannot at all be battered into a single set of elements. Not the relationship of an element to a set, but of a part to a whole ought to be taken as a basis for the analysis of a continuum." (Hermann Weyl, "Reimanns geometrische Ideen, ihre Auswirkungen und ihre Verknüpfung mit der Gruppentheorie", 1925)

"To say that mathematics in general has been reduced to logic hints at some new firming up of mathematics at its foundations. This is misleading. Set theory is less settled and more conjectural than the classical mathematical superstructure than can be founded upon it." (Willard van Orman Quine, "Elementary Logic", 1941)

"The emphasis on mathematical methods seems to be shifted more towards combinatorics and set theory - and away from the algorithm of differential equations which dominates mathematical physics." (John von Neumann & Oskar Morgenstern, "Theory of Games and Economic Behavior", 1944)

"But, despite their remoteness from sense experience, we do have something like a perception of the objects of set theory, as is seen from the fact that the axioms force themselves upon us as being true. I don't see any reason why we should have less confidence in this kind of perception, i.e., in mathematical intuition, than in sense perception, which induces us to build up physical theories and to expect that future sense perception will agree with them and, moreover, to believe that a question not decidable now has meaning and may be decided in future." (Kurt Gödel, "What is Cantor’s Continuum problem?", American Mathematical Monthly 54, 1947)

"Categorical algebra has developed in recent years as an effective method of organizing parts of mathematics. Typically, this sort of organization uses notions such as that of the category G of all groups. [...] This raises the problem of finding some axiomatization of set theory - or of some foundational discipline like set theory - which will be adequate and appropriate to realizing this intent. This problem may turn out to have revolutionary implications vis-`a-vis the accepted views of the role of set theory." (Saunders Mac Lane, "Categorical algebra and set-theoretic foundations", 1967)

"In set theory, perhaps more than in any other branch of mathematics, it is vital to set up a collection of symbolic abbreviations for various logical concepts. Because the basic assumptions of set theory are absolutely minimal, all but the most trivial assertions about sets tend to be logically complex, and a good system of abbreviations helps to make otherwise complex statements."  (Keith Devlin, "Sets, Functions, and Logic: An Introduction to Abstract Mathematics", 1979)

"Set theory is peculiarly important [...] because mathematics can be exhibited as involving nothing but set-theoretical propositions about set-theoretical entities." (David M Armstrong, "A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility", 1989)

"At the basis of the distance concept lies, for example, the concept of convergent point sequence and their defined limits, and one can, by choosing these ideas as those fundamental to point set theory, eliminate the notions of distance." (Felix Hausdorff)

01 March 2020

On Principles IV: On Equifinality

"Of course, we must be careful about what has to be ‘known’ and ‘judged’ and ‘willed’. This problem seems rather easy to answer in the light of morphological restitutions Here the end to be attained is the normal organisation ; that ‘means’ towards this end are known and found may seem very strange, but it is a fact; and it in a fact also, in the case of what we have called ‘equifinal regulations’, that different means leading to one and the same final state may be known and adopted." (Hans Driesch, "The Science and Philosophy of the Organism", 1908)

"Analysis shows that closed systems cannot behave equifinally. This is the reason why equifinality is found in inanimate nature only in exceptional cases. However, in open systems, which are exchanging materials with the environment, in so far as they attain a steady state, the latter is independent of the initial conditions, or is equifinal.[...] Steady state systems show equifinality, in sharp contrast to closed systems in equilibrium where the final state depends on the components given at the beginning of the process." (Ludwig von Bertalanffy, "The Theory of Open Systems in Physics and Biology", Science Vol. 111, 1950)

"Two qualifications of this observation are in order, First, it is by no means true that every ‘open system’ is able to exhibit equifinality. ‘Equifinality’ as a property of all open systems has never been rigorously defined. If one assumes a rigorous definition in terms of a unique steady state, then, of course, this is realizable only on paper […]" (Joseph M Yoffey, "Homeostatic Mechanisms", 1958)

"Open systems, in contrast to closed systems, exhibit a principle of equifinality, that is, a tendency to achieve a final state independent of initial conditions. In other words, open systems tend to 'resist' perturbations that take them away from some steady state. They can exhibit homeostasis." (Anatol Rapaport, "The Uses of Mathematical Isomorphism in General System Theory", 1972)

"Every system of whatever size must maintain its own structure and must deal with a dynamic environment, i.e., the system must strike a proper balance between stability and change. The cybernetic mechanisms for stability (i.e., homeostasis, negative feedback, autopoiesis, equifinality) and change (i.e., positive feedback, algedonodes, self-organization) are found in all viable systems." (Barry Clemson, "Cybernetics: A New Management Tool", 1984)

"Particular landforms or surface morphologies may be generated, in some cases, by several different processes, sets of environmental controls, or developmental histories. This convergence to similar forms despite variations in processes and controls is called equifinality." (Jonathan Phillips, "Simplexity and the Reinvention of Equifinality", Geographical Analysis Vol. 29 (1), 1997)

"Equifinality is the principle which states that morphology alone cannot be used to reconstruct the mode of origin of a landform on the grounds that identical landforms can be produced by a number of alternative processes, process assemblages or process histories. Different processes may lead to an apparent similarity in the forms produced. For example, sea-level change, tectonic uplift, climatic change, change in source of sediment or water or change in storage may all lead to river incision and a convergence of form." (Olav Slaymaker, "Equifinality", 2004)

"Principle of Equifinality: If a steady state is reached in an open system, it is independent of the initial conditions, and determined only by the system parameters, i.e. rates of reaction and transport." (Kevin Adams & Charles Keating, "Systems of systems engineering", 2012)

26 July 2018

On Topology IV (More on Topology)

"The young mathematical disciple 'topology' might be of some help in making psychology a real science." (Kurt Lewin, Principles of topological psychology, 1936)

"Topology provides the synergetic means of ascertaining the values of any system of experiences. Topology is the science of fundamental pattern and structural relationships of event constellations." (R Buckminster Fuller, "Operating Manual for Spaceship Earth", 1969)

"Topology is not ‘designed to guide us’ in structure. It is this structure." (Jacques Lacan, "L’Étourdit", 1972)

"No other theory known to science [other than superstring theory] uses such powerful mathematics at such a fundamental level. […] because any unified field theory first must absorb the Riemannian geometry of Einstein’s theory and the Lie groups coming from quantum field theory. […] The new mathematics, which is responsible for the merger of these two theories, is topology, and it is responsible for accomplishing the seemingly impossible task of abolishing the infinities of a quantum theory of gravity." (Michio Kaku, "Hyperspace", 1995)

"Topology makes it possible to explain the general structure of the set of solutions without even knowing their analytic expression." (Michael I. Monastyrsky, "Riemann, Topology, and Physics" 2nd Ed., 2008)

"At the basis of the distance concept lies, for example, the concept of convergent point sequence and their defined limits, and one can, by choosing these ideas as those fundamental to point set theory, eliminate the notions of distance." (Felix Hausdorff)

"In every subject one looks for the topological and algebraic structures involved, since these structures form a unifying core for the most varied branches of mathematics." (K Weise and H Noack, "Aspects of Topology")

"Mathematicians do not study objects, but relations between objects. Thus, they are free to replace some objects by others so long as the relations remain unchanged. Content to them is irrelevant: they are interested in form only." (Henri Poincaré)

"Poetry and code - and mathematics - make us read differently from other forms of writing. Written poetry makes the silent reader read three kinds of pattern at once; code moves the reader from a static to an active, interactive and looped domain; while algebraic topology allows us to read qualitative forms and their transformations." (Stephanie Strickland)

"Topology is the study of the modal relations of spatial figures and the laws of connectivity, mutual position, and ordering of points, lines, surfaces, and solids and their parts independently of measure and magnitude relations." (Johann B Listing)
Related Posts Plugin for WordPress, Blogger...

On Leonhard Euler

"I have been able to solve a few problems of mathematical physics on which the greatest mathematicians since Euler have struggled in va...