Quotes and Resources Related to Mathematics, (Mathematical) Sciences and Mathematicians
09 May 2019
On Proofs (2010 - 2019)
On Proofs (2000 - 2009)
On Proofs (1950 - 1974)
“You have to guess the mathematical theorem before you prove it: you have to guess the idea of the proof before you carry through the details. You have to combine observations and follow analogies: you have to try and try again. The result of the mathematician’s creative work is demonstrative reasoning, a proof; but the proof is discovered by plausible reasoning, by guessing” (George Polya, “Mathematics and plausible reasoning” Vol. 1, 1954)
"We speak in terms of ‘acceptance’, ‘confidence’, and ‘probability’, not ‘proof’. If by proof it is meant the establishment of eternal and absolute truth, open to no possible exception or modification, then proof has no place in the natural sciences." (George G Simpson, “Life: An Introduction to Biology”, 1957)
"It is sometimes said of two expositions of one and the same mathematical proof that the one is simpler or more elegant than the other. This is a distinction which has little interest from the point of view of the theory of knowledge; it does not fall within the province of logic, but merely indicates a preference of an aesthetic or pragmatic character." (Karl Popper, "The Logic of Scientific Discovery", 1959)
"The most natural way to give an independence proof is to establish a model with the required properties. This is not the only way to proceed since one can attempt to deal directly and analyze the structure of proofs. However, such an approach to set theoretic questions is unnatural since all our intuition come from our belief in the natural, almost physical model of the mathematical universe." (Paul J Cohen, "Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis", 1966)
"It is characteristic of science that the full explanations are often seized in their essence by the percipient scientist long in advance of any possible proof." (John Desmond Bernal, "The Origin of Life", 1967)
"A diagram is worth a thousand proofs." (Carl E Linderholm, “Mathematics Made Difficult”, 1971)
"In many cases a dull proof can be supplemented by a geometric analogue so simple and beautiful that the truth of a theorem is almost seen at a glance." (Martin Gardner, "Mathematical Games", Scientific American, 1973)
See also:
Proofs I, II, III, IV, V, VII, VIII, IX
Theorems I, II, III, IV, V, VI, VII, VIII, IX, X
On Proofs (1850-1899)
"We must never assume that which is incapable of proof.” (George H Lewes, “The Physiology of Common Life” Vol. 2, 1860)
"Few will deny that even in the first scientific instruction in mathematics the most rigorous method is to be given preference over all others. Especially will every teacher prefer a consistent proof to one which is based on fallacies or proceeds in a vicious circle, indeed it will be morally impossible for the teacher to present a proof of the latter kind consciously and thus in a sense deceive his pupils. Notwithstanding these objectionable so-called proofs, so far as the foundation and the development of the system is concerned, predominate in our textbooks to the present time. Perhaps it will be answered, that rigorous proof is found too difficult for the pupil’s power of comprehension. Should this be anywhere the case, - which would only indicate some defect in the plan or treatment of the whole, - the only remedy would be to merely state the theorem in a historic way, and forego a proof with the frank confession that no proof has been found which could be comprehended by the pupil; a remedy which is ever doubtful and should only be applied in the case of extreme necessity. But this remedy is to be preferred to a proof which is no proof, and is therefore either wholly unintelligible to the pupil, or deceives him with an appearance of knowledge which opens the door to all superficiality and lack of scientific method." (Hermann G Grassmann, "Stücke aus dem Lehrbuche der Arithmetik", 1861)
"The mathematician starts with a few propositions, the proof of which is so obvious that they are called self-evident, and the rest of his work consists of subtle deductions from them. The teaching of languages, at any rate as ordinarily practised, is of the same general nature: authority and tradition furnish the data, and the mental operations are deductive." (Thomas H Huxley, 1869)
“Simplification of modes of proof is not merely an indication of advance in our knowledge of a subject, but is also the surest guarantee of readiness for farther progress.“ (Lord Kelvin, “Elements of Natural Philosophy”, 1873)
“’Divide et impera’ is as true in algebra as in statecraft; but no less true and even more fertile is the maxim ‘auge et impera’. The more to do or to prove, the easier the doing or the proof.” (James J Sylvester, “Proof of the Fundamental Theorem of Invariants”, Philosophic Magazine, 1878)
"The aim of proof is, in fact, not merely to place the truth of a proposition beyond all doubt, but also to afford us insight into the dependence of one truth upon another. After we have convinced ourselves that a boulder is immovable, by trying unsuccessfully to move it, there remains the further question, what is it that supports it so securely." (Gottlob Frege," The Foundations of Arithmetic", 1884)
“That which is provable, ought not to be believed in science without proof” (Richard Dedekind, “Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?”, 1888)
“Pure mathematics proves itself a royal science both through its content and form, which contains within itself the cause of its being and its methods of proof. For in complete independence mathematics creates for itself the object of which it treats, its magnitudes and laws, its formulas and symbols.” (Christian H Dillmann, „Die Mathematik die Fackelträgerin einer neuen Zeit“, 1889)
“If men of science owe anything to us, we may learn much from them that is essential. For they can show how to test proof, how to secure fulness and soundness in induction, how to restrain and to employ with safety hypothesis and analogy.” (Lord John Acton, [Lecture] “The Study of History”, 1895)
“The folly of mistaking a paradox for a discovery, a metaphor for a proof, a torrent of verbiage for a spring of capital truths, and oneself for an oracle, is inborn in us.” (Paul Valéry, 1895)
"Just give me the insights. I can always come up with the proofs!" (Bernhard Riemann)
"Analogy cannot serve as proof." (Louis Pasteur)
See also:
Proofs I, II, III, IV, VI, VII, VIII, IX
Theorems I, II, III, IV, V, VI, VII, VIII, IX, X
On Proofs (1800 - 1849)
"Mathematical proofs, like diamonds, are hard and clear, and will be touched with nothing but strict reasoning." (John Locke, 1824)
"Mathematics in gross, it is plain, are a grievance in natural philosophy, and with reason. […] Mathematical proofs are out of the reach of topical arguments, and are not to be attacked by the equivocal use of words or declamation, that make so great a part of other discourses; nay, even of controversies." (John Locke, 1824)
"Logic does not pretend to teach the surgeon what are the symptoms which indicate a violent death. This he must learn from his own experience and observation, or from that of others, his predecessors in his peculiar science. But logic sits in judgment on the sufficiency of that observation and experience to justify his rules, and on the sufficiency of his rules to justify his conduct. It does not give him proofs, but teaches him what makes them proofs, and how he is to judge of them." (John Stuart Mill, "A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a Connected View of the Principles of Evidence, and the Methods of Scientific Investigation", 1843)
On Proofs (1600 - 1800)
"There have been only Mathematicians who were able to find some proofs, that is to say some sure and certain reasons." (René Descartes)
"The essential quality of a proof is to compel belief." (Pierre de Fermat)
“But the most powerful proof of the reality of phenomena (a proof which is, indeed, sufficient by itself) is success in predicting future phenomena from those which are past and present, whether the prediction be founded upon the success, so far, of a reason or hypothesis, or upon custom so far observed.” (Gottfried W Leibniz, "De Modo Distinguendi phenomena realia ab imaginariis" [“On the Method of Distinguishing Real from Imaginary Phenomena”], cca. 1684)
"Some facts can be seen more clearly by example than by proof.” (Leonard Euler)
On Proofs (500 - 1499)
“Reason may be employed in two ways to establish a point: first for the purpose of furnishing sufficient proof of some principle, as in natural science, where sufficient proof can be brought to show that the movement of the heavens is always of uniform velocity. Reason is employed in another way, not as furnishing a sufficient proof of a principle, but as confirming an already established principle, by showing the congruity of its results [...]” (Saint Thomas Aquinas, “Summa Theologica“, 1485)
Proofs ( - 499 AD)
"Analysis is the obtaining of the thing sought by assuming it and so reasoning up to an admitted truth; synthesis is the obtaining of the thing sought by reasoning up to the inference and proof of it." (Eudoxus, cca. 4th century BC)
"Analysis is a method where one assumes that which is sought, and from this, through a series of implications, arrives at something which is agreed upon on the basis of synthesis; because in analysis, one assumes that which is sought to be known, proved, or constructed, and examines what this is a consequence of and from what this latter follows, so that by backtracking we end up with something that is already known or is part of the starting points of the theory; we call such a method analysis; it is, in a sense, a solution in reversed direction. In synthesis we work in the opposite direction: we assume the last result of the analysis to be true. Then we put the causes from analysis in their natural order, as consequences, and by putting these together we obtain the proof or the construction of that which is sought. We call this synthesis." (Pappus of Alexandria, cca. 4th century BC)
"In analysis, we start from what is required, we take it for granted, and we draw consequences from it, and consequences from the consequences, till we reach a point that we can use as starting point in synthesis. For in analysis we assume what is required to be done as already done (what is sought as already found, what we have to prove as true). We inquire from what antecedent the desired result could be derived; then we inquire again what could be the antecedent of that antecedent, and so on, until passing from antecedent to antecedent, we come eventually upon something already known or admittedly true. This procedure we call analysis, or solution backwards, or regressive reasoning." (Pappus of Alexandria, cca. 4th century BC)
"Now analysis is of two kinds; the one is the analysis of the ‘problems to prove’ and aims at establishing true theorems; the other is the analysis of the ‘problems to find’ and aims at finding the unknown."
"It is not possible to find in all geometry more difficult and more intricate questions or more simple and lucid explanations [than those given by Archimedes]. Some ascribe this to his natural genius; while others think that incredible effort and toil produced these, to all appearance, easy and unlaboured results. No amount of investigation of yours would succeed in attaining the proof, and yet, once seen, you immediately believe you would have discovered it; by so smooth and so rapid a path he leads you to the conclusion required." (Plutarch, cca. 1st century)
07 May 2019
On Beauty: Beauty and Mathematics (2000-2019)
“Elegance and simplicity should remain important criteria in judging mathematics, but the applicability and consequences of a result are also important, and sometimes these criteria conflict. I believe that some fundamental theorems do not admit simple elegant treatments, and the proofs of such theorems may of necessity be long and complicated. Our standards of rigor and beauty must be sufficiently broad and realistic to allow us to accept and appreciate such results and their proofs. As mathematicians we will inevitably use such theorems when it is necessary in the practice our trade; our philosophy and aesthetics should reflect this reality.” (Michael Aschbacher, “Highly complex proofs and implications”, 2005)
“The immediate evidence from the natural world may seem to be chaotic and without any inner regularity, but mathematics reveals that under the surface the world of nature has an unexpected simplicity - an extraordinary beauty and order.” (William Byers, “How Mathematicians Think”, 2007)
“I enjoy mathematics so much because it has a strange kind of unearthly beauty. There is a strong feeling of pleasure, hard to describe, in thinking through an elegant proof, and even greater pleasure in discovering a proof not previously known.” (Martin Gardner, 2008)
“In mathematics, beauty is a very important ingredient. Beauty exists in mathematics as in architecture and other things. It is a difficult thing to define but it is something you recognise when you see it. It certainly has to have elegance, simplicity, structure and form. All sorts of things make up real beauty. There are many different kinds of beauty and the same is true of mathematical theorems. Beauty is an important criterion in mathematics because basically there is a lot of choice in what you can do in mathematics and science. It determines what you regard as important and what is not.” (Michael Atiyah, 2009)
“Mathematics is the music of reason. To do mathematics is to engage in an act of discovery and conjecture, intuition and inspiration; to be in a state of confusion - not because it makes no sense to you, but because you gave it sense and you still don't understand what your creation is up to; to have a break-through idea; to be frustrated as an artist; to be awed and overwhelmed by an almost painful beauty; to be alive, damn it.” (Paul Lockhart, A Mathematician's Lament, 2009)
“Mathematicians seek a certain kind of beauty. Perhaps mathematical beauty is a constant - as far as the contents of mathematics are concerned - and yet the forms this beauty takes are certainly cultural. And while the history of mathematics surely is many stranded, one of its most important strands is formed by such cultural forms of mathematical beauty.” (Reviel Netz, “Ludic Proof: Greek Mathematics and the Alexandrian Aesthetic”, 2009)
“Mathematicians are sometimes described as living in an ideal world of beauty and harmony. Instead, our world is torn apart by inconsistencies, plagued by non sequiturs and, worst of all, made desolate and empty by missing links between words, and between symbols and their referents; we spend our lives patching and repairing it. Only when the last crack disappears are we rewarded by brief moments of harmony and joy.” (Alexandre V Borovik, “Mathematics under the Microscope: Notes on Cognitive Aspects of Mathematical Practice”, 2009)
“What is the basis of this interest in beauty? Is it the same in both mathematics and science? Is it rational, in either case, to expect or demand that the products of the discipline satisfy such a criterion? Is there an underlying assumption that the proper business of mathematics and science is to discover what can be discovered about reality and that truth - mathematical and physical - when seen as clearly as possible, must be beautiful? If the demand for beauty stems from some such assumption, is the assumption itself an article of blind faith? If such an assumption is not its basis, what is?” (Raymond S Nickerson, “Mathematical Reasoning: Patterns, Problems, Conjectures, and Proofs”, 2010)
"You do not study mathematics because it helps you build a bridge. You study mathematics because it is the poetry of the universe. Its beauty transcends mere things." (Jonathan D Farley, 2011)
On Beauty: Beauty and Mathematics VI (Unsourced)
"Mathematics has beauty and romance. It's not a boring place to be, the mathematical world. It's an extraordinary place; it's worth spending time there." (Marcus Du Sautoy)
"When I am working on a problem I never think about beauty. I only think about how to solve the problem. But when I have finished, if the solution is not beautiful, I know it is wrong." (Buckminster Fuller)
"[…] the feeling of mathematical beauty, of the harmony of numbers and of forms, of geometric elegance. It is a genuinely esthetic feeling, which all mathematicians know. And this is sensitivity." (Henri Poincaré)
“The scientist does not study nature because it is useful; he studies it because he delights in it, and he delights in it because it is beautiful. If nature were not beautiful, it would not be worth knowing, and if nature were not worth knowing, life would not be worth living. Of course I do not here speak of that beauty that strikes the senses, the beauty of qualities and appearances; not that I undervalue such beauty, far from it, but it has nothing to do with science; I mean that profounder beauty which comes from the harmonious order of the parts, and which a pure intelligence can grasp.” (Henri Poincaré)
"All mathematicians share ... a sense of amazement over the infinite depth and the mysterious beauty and usefulness of mathematics." (Martin Gardner)
"There are some traits all mathematicians share. An obvious one is a sense of amazement over the infinite depth and the mysterious beauty and usefulness of mathematics." (Martin Gardner)
"I was struck by the art with which mathematicians remove, reject, and little by little eliminate everything that is not necessary for expressing the absolute with the least possible number of terms, while preserving in the arrangement of these terms a discrimination, a parallelism, a symmetry which seems to be the visible elegance and beauty of an eternal idea. (Edgar Quinet)
On Thresholds (From Fiction to Science-Ficttion)
"For many men that stumble at the threshold Are well foretold that danger lurks within." (William Shakespeare, "King Henry th...